The dynamic child

Chapter 11. The dynamic child

children’s psychological development and its application to the delivery of care

Helen E. Rushforth



LEARNING OUTCOMES



• Recognise the importance of an understanding of the role of cognitive developmental theory within children’s nursing.


• Gain enhanced insight into the ways in which children conceptualise health, illness and their internal bodies, and be able to use this information to offer enhanced explanations to children and families.


• Gain an appreciation of children’s language and personality development, and be able to articulate the ways in which these theories can also contribute to the care given by the children’s nurse.


• Develop insight into the critical appraisal of psychological theory and its application to care delivery.



Introduction


The purpose of this chapter is to offer readers an overview of key theories in children’s psychological development, and to consider these in terms of their relevance to children’s nursing practice. Particular emphasis is placed on cognitive developmental theory, as this appears to have the most direct relevance for care delivery. To illustrate this, an exploration of the ways in which children conceptualise health and illness is offered as a key example of the application of theory to practice. Consideration is also given to the related areas of language and personality development, which also have important implications for the delivery of child health care.

A range of developmental theories is explored within this chapter, and readers are encouraged to critically consider the appropriateness of each as a tool to guide their future professional development. Perhaps the most important guiding principle in selecting an appropriate theory to underpin practice is to consider the congruence of the theories offered with other contemporary notions of childhood, children’s rights, and child healthcare delivery. Increasingly, recognition is being made of children’s potential to be ‘active participants’ in their health care, rather than passive recipients. Thus it is particularly appropriate to question the continued dominance of many theories, particularly in cognitive development, which cast children in a primarily dependent role. If developmental psychology is to continue to have meaning for the healthcare practitioners of the 21st century, then it must reflect contemporary views of childhood in other domains.


The nature–nurture debate


For any student considering developmental psychology, the nature–nurture debate is a key concept that underpins the work of almost all the major contributors. Thus an understanding of the nature–nurture concept is a useful starting point. Santrock (1999 p 21) defines nature as ‘an organism’s biological inheritance’ and nurture as ‘environmental experiences’. Therefore, the nature perspective would argue that a personality characteristic, e.g. moral behaviour, will develop naturally over time irrespective of external influences. By contrast, the nurture perspective would take the position that morality is a phenomenon that is learned, and thus is dependent on external stimuli.



Cognitive development


Although developmental psychology considers a variety of important domains, there is little doubt that the topic with the greatest influence for the child healthcare practitioner is that of cognitive development. From the outset it is important to acknowledge the dominance within this field of Jean Piaget (1896–1980); his profound influence on our understanding of childhood cannot be overestimated. However, although Piaget’s invaluable contribution to developmental psychology is both acknowledged and valued, it is important to question the appropriateness of the domination of some of his assertions within the theory and practice of child healthcare delivery. Consequently, this chapter balances the Piagetian perspective with the views of other cognitive developmental psychologists, particularly Lev Vygotsky (1896–1934), thereby offering alternative tools to guide practice, which may be more congruent with other contemporary views of childhood.


Piagetian perspectives




Sensory motor stage: from birth to around 2 years


Piaget identifies this first stage as characterised by the links formed between the infant and the environment as the infant comes to understand the relationship between actions, sensation and movement. Piaget divided the stage into six subsections (for more detail see Piaget & Inhelder 1969 pp 4–12). These stages characterise the infant’s development from being primarily reflexive/reactive (stage 1) through processes of trial and error, experiment and reinforcement (stages 2–5), to finally being able to actively understand and manipulate aspects of his or her world (stage 6). In other words, the infant has a gradually increasing awareness of the relationship between action and effect.

Piaget saw a key concept within this stage as something he called ‘object permanence’. This means that for the younger infant ‘out of sight’ is also ‘out of mind’. In contrast, older infants (Piaget argued from around 8 months) realise that an object exists even when it cannot be seen. Also, throughout this first stage the child is described as egocentric, i.e. ‘the child’s initial universe is entirely centred on his [sic] own body’ (Piaget & Inhelder 1969 p 13).


Preoperational stage: from around 2 years to around 7 years


Piaget viewed the next two stages as a vital period of transition. At the beginning of this second stage, Piaget argued that the child’s behaviour is characterised by actions; by its end the child will have reached the level of operations, summarised by Santrock (1999 p 203) as ‘internalised sets of actions that allow the child to do mentally what was done physically before’. Piaget regarded achieving this as of pivotal importance and saw the preoperational period as dominated by organisation and preparation towards becoming ‘operational’ (Piaget & Inhelder 1969 p 96). Consequently, the stage tends to be characterised negatively, by what children are not yet able to do, rather than what they can. Examples include their perceived inability to classify objects into groups, to think logically and to engage in moral reasoning. A key skill not yet achieved is that of conservation, i.e. the ability to realise that something might ‘stay the same’ despite a change in appearance. For example, a preoperational child would think the amount of juice in a short, fat glass becomes ‘more’ when poured into a tall, thin glass (see also Channel 4 Television, 2001 and Santrock, 2009).

Also within this stage is a continued focus on the child’s egocentricity, characterised particularly by the inability to be able to see the world from another’s point of view or to distinguish another’s point of view from their own (both visually and intellectually). Closely linked to this is Piaget’s belief that these children could not conceptualise a world beyond their direct experience, i.e. what he or she had actually seen or experienced. Practically applied, it can be seen how such beliefs can limit perceptions of the preoperational child’s abilities in a whole variety of conceptual domains. Piaget also noted that these children display animism, the attribution of ‘life’ to non-live objects.


Concrete operational stage: from around 7 years to around 11 years


Piaget saw this stage as characterised by children becoming ‘operational’, and thus being able to do many of the activities that they were working towards in the preoperational stage. He argued that operational children are capable of logical, systematic thought, and able to ‘conserve’ concepts such as number, mass, length, weight and volume. They are also able to classify and seriate objects/items, and to understand logical relationships between them. However, Piaget felt at this ‘concrete’ stage that children could only understand problems related to direct experience; they are not seen as capable of abstract or hypothetical thought, or the manipulation of variables.


Formal operational stage: from around 12 years onwards


Piaget used the term ‘propositional operations’ to describe this final stage. He regarded these skills as congruent with preparation for adolescence, with the child able to think in abstract terms and capable of ‘the handling of hypotheses and reasoning with regard to propositions removed from concrete and present operation’ (Piaget & Inhelder 1969 p 131). Thus young people are able systematically to explore the solutions to an abstract or hypothetical problem, including everything from algebra to decisions concerning their future! An important extension of this is described as ‘reflective abstraction’ – self-awareness in relation to one’s own strategies and thoughts.


Other key concepts in Piaget’s work


These four stages are the centre-piece of Piaget’s theories of childhood but many other important concepts also exist within his works. Those with particular relevance for child health practitioners can be summarised as follows:


• The way in which children think is fundamentally different from the way in which adults think.


• Development is fundamentally reliant on the concept of maturation, i.e. developmental pace is predetermined, and the teacher cannot accelerate this process.


• The child’s understanding derives from self-directed actions upon the physical world. Thus, the teacher’s role is limited to constructing learning opportunities, and it is primarily through the child’s independent interaction with the world that learning takes place.


• The child develops in a series of ‘discrete stages’ like ‘caterpillar, chrysalis, butterfly’, as opposed to a continuous development such as ‘kitten to cat’.


Within Piaget’s theories three additional key concepts underpin a child’s emergent understanding of the world (derived from Meadows 2006, Piaget, 1929, Piaget, 1930, Piaget and Inhelder, 1969, Santrock, 2009 and Vacik et al., 2001):


Scheme or schema: the cognitive structure whereby the child organises his or her understanding of a particular concept.


Assimilation: new information is incorporated into the child’s existing schema, i.e. that which the child already knows.


Accommodation: existing understanding ceases to be sufficient to make sense of the world. The schema is reorganised to understand the world in a new way.

To illustrate these somewhat abstract concepts, it might be helpful to consider an example. Imagine for a moment the child seeing a picture of a zebra for the first time.


• If the child already has a schema for horses, he or she might very well suppose that the zebra is another type of horse.


• This then would be assimilation: the child has taken the new information and incorporated it into his or her existing schema.


• However, through education and/or experience, the child will learn that the new animal is not a horse but actually something rather different, i.e. a zebra. Therefore the child develops a new schema for the zebra (and perhaps a wider schema for African animals). Thus a change in the child’s understanding of the world has taken place, i.e. accommodation.


• Successful accommodation was viewed as essential to ongoing cognitive development, and enabled the child to achieve what Piaget called equilibrium.


• However, the risks inherent within the process are that from time to time misunderstanding will occur, e.g. instead of accommodation, the child happily goes on to describe an animal as a ‘stripy horse’.


B9780702031830100116/reflect.jpg is missingReflect on your practice


Before reading further, think about the following situation. Suppose you are admitting Jack, a 5-year-old child, to hospital for a course of intravenous antibiotics due to pneumonia:


• Consider Piaget’s views on cognitive development. In what ways might your care of Jack be influenced if you assumed all of Piaget’s assertions to be true?


• Think particularly about what explanations you might give to Jack regarding the treatment and care he will receive?


• Do you feel entirely comfortable with the approach you would take, or is there some conflict with your current experience and understanding of hospitalised children?


Influences of Piagetian theory on contemporary practice


Piagetian theories influenced the delivery of child health care throughout much of the latter half of the 20th century and many of his views continue to be profoundly influential. For example, in the care of infants, Piaget’s theory of ‘object permanence’ suggests that under about 8 months a child does not realise an object still exists when it cannot be seen, a theory applied not only to inanimate objects but also to people. Thus it has been argued in some centres that younger infants will not be unduly distressed when separated from their parents. So although unrestricted parental visiting is now more or less universally accepted within child health care, the parents of infants continue to be excluded in some care settings from anaesthetic rooms, recovery rooms and a variety of other procedures, on the grounds that this age group of children won’t be unduly distressed by parental absence.

For the ‘pre-operational’ child, assumptions are often made about what the child is or is not able to understand about an illness, procedure or investigation. A Piagetian perspective would assume that children under the age of about seven were incapable of conceptualising their internal anatomy, and thus suggests that it may be pointless to attempt any realistic explanation of an internal procedure. As will be discussed in detail later, such guidelines were heavily influential during the 1970s and 1980s. A Piagetian stance would also contend that other misconceptions are inevitable and cannot be overcome until a child reaches a certain point of maturation. Examples include ‘immanent justice’ (Santrock 2009), which is the belief that pain or injury is a punishment, and ‘overgeneralising contagion’, e.g. believing cancer is ‘catching’.

Even as the child becomes ‘operational’, assumptions continue to be made. As Piaget asserts that the concrete operational child cannot hypothesise, look meaningfully into the future or make decisions based on abstract concepts, it is often suggested that, until mid to late adolescence, a child cannot make an informed decision about what might be in his or her ‘best interests’. Such beliefs have historically limited children being offered any meaningful involvement in decisions regarding their care – a situation which continues to exist in some care settings even today.

Thus it can be seen how important it is to gain an accurate picture of the extent to which Piaget’s beliefs represent ‘truth’. If there are doubts about some aspects of his theory, then such doubts must inevitably be extended to the application of Piagetian principles to care delivery. It is therefore important both to review the literature that takes a more critical view of Piaget’s work and also to consider different theoretical perspectives that might offer alternative tools to guide contemporary practice.


Critiquing Piaget


The 1970s and 1980s were characterised by a series of challenges to Piaget’s perspective on child development, with a whole range of authors suggesting that Piagetian theory unreasonably limited our beliefs in children’s abilities and that, in reality, children were capable of far more than Piaget gave them credit for.

In respect of the preoperational child, various studies have demonstrated the ability of young infants to visually recognise their parents and distinguish them from strangers (see Taylor et al 1999 pp 25–26). Similarly, Santrock, 1999 and Santrock, 2009 and Bee & Boyd (2008) describe studies where infants demonstrate learning at just a few weeks old, far younger than Piaget would have accepted that these infants could proactively manipulate their environment. In one example, Santrock (1999 p 153) cites the work of Rovee-Colyer (1987), who took infants at just a few months old and tied their foot to a ribbon that moved a mobile. Weeks later, when placed under the mobile, the infants will once again kick in an attempt to move the mobile, despite no ribbon being in place.

Similar critiques of Piagetian theory are found in respect of the preoperational child. For example, in his study of egocentricity, Piaget devised a test known as the ‘three mountains experiment’ (Piaget & Inhelder 1956). The child was shown a three-dimensional model of three differently coloured mountains, positioned so that clearly different views of the mountains were visible from each of the four sides of the model (see Piaget & Inhelder 1969 or Santrock 1999 p 205 for more detail). The child was given a series of four two-dimensional drawings representing the view from each side of the model, and asked to ‘work out’ which drawing represented the view of a doll positioned on the opposite side of the model to the child. The fact that most children aged under 7 were unable to do this was central to Piaget’s persistent belief in their egocentricity; their inability to see the world from another’s point of view.

Yet in contrast, Donaldson (1978), one of Piaget’s foremost critics, constructed another experiment where children were far more successful, using an intersection of two walls in a ‘cross shape’ (see Donaldson 1978 pp 21–22 or Taylor et al 1999 p 58 for more detail). Two policeman models were positioned in such a way that they could see behind most of the walls but not all. In this study, children who got the three-mountain test wrong were frequently able to position a naughty doll so that the policemen were unable to see her; clearly they had to understand what the world looked like from the policemen’s perspective to do this. Perhaps the key difference, Donaldson suggests, is that this experiment ‘made sense’ to the child and so was more readily understood. Clearly if children below 7 years are able to see another’s point of view there are major implications for beliefs regarding their egocentricity.

B9780702031830100116/activity.jpg is missingActivity


Gaining evidence of children’s ability to see the world from another’s perspective may be simpler even than Donaldson suggests:


• Take a favourite toy belonging to a child as young as 3 and position it facing the wall. Ask the child what the toy can see?


• Now move the toy to face in different directions in the room, and ask the same question.

Many 3- and 4-year-old children will happily tell you what the toy can or can’t see. Yet these children are up to 4 years younger than those Piaget claimed were still egocentric.

In another of her critiques of Piaget’s work, Donaldson also challenged some of his conservation experiments. For example, Piaget had conducted a study where children are asked to view two identical rows of sweets and say whether the rows are the same. The experimenter then repositions the sweets in one row so they are further apart, but leaves the same number. When re-questioned in Piaget’s study, many children under seven insisted the row where the sweets have been moved now contained ‘more’. Yet when Donaldson (1978) replicated the study using a ‘naughty teddy’ to move the sweets, significantly fewer children got the answer wrong than in a control group where, like in Piaget’s original study, the researcher moved the sweets. Donaldson argued this was because the answer ‘still being the same’ now ‘made sense’, unlike the Piagetian version in which many children assumed the answer must now be different. Indeed, central to Donaldson’s (1978) theories about Piaget was a recurrent theme that his experiments were designed in such a way that the children were often set up to fail, and that as a consequence children’s abilities at a given age/stage were at significant risk of being underestimated.

For the concrete operational child, again, numerous studies challenge Piaget’s perspectives. One particular study with clear healthcare implications is by Alderson (1993). She interviewed 120 children, many of whom fell into Piaget’s concrete operational age group, and demonstrated the ability of several of these children to make carefully considered and informed choices about non-essential surgery.

It is beyond the scope of this chapter to illuminate the dozens of similar examples of experiments that call into question many of Piaget’s findings (see Bee and Boyd, 2008, Berger, 2008, Berk, 2006 and Berk, 2008, Donaldson, 1978 and Santrock, 2009 for more details). It is important to stress, however, that it is not Piaget’s fundamental assertions about the systematic way in which children develop cognitively that are necessarily being challenged; his model continues to offer extremely valuable insight into the sequential ways in which children develop. Rather it is the nativist domination in his theories that has become the key focus of his critics, i.e. the:


• inevitability of constraints imposed by age and maturation


• protracted timescale taken to reach each developmental stage


• impossibility of accelerating the developmental process by education


• minimal credence given to the influences of experience, society and culture


• fact that, translated into practical terms, such beliefs have the potential to limit opportunities – given to younger children in particular – to understand their world and make sense of their experiences.

However, if these critiques of Piaget’s work cast doubt on his theories in this way, then there are also inevitably important implications for many of the traditional applications of his theory to care delivery. Thus it may no longer be safe to assume that a 4-month-old baby can go for surgery alone and not be adversely affected by parental separation before he or she is asleep. Similarly, it might be unsafe to assume that a 4-year-old cannot understand an explanation of his or her heart surgery, or that a 9-year-old is unable to contribute meaningfully to a decision to undergo leg lengthening. It is therefore vital that such assumptions are carefully considered in light of the research that casts doubt on aspects of Piagetian theory, and also in the light of the views of alternative theorists, who may offer a more positive interpretation of younger children’s cognitive development.


Carey: ‘novice to expert shift’ theory


One of the key theorists who offers a very different view to that of Piaget is Carey (1985). In her ‘novice to expert shift’ theory, Carey – writing from an empirical perspective – argued that there is nothing fundamentally different about the way in which children and adults think and come to an understanding of the world. She argued that it is knowledge, not maturation, that is the key. Where only a little knowledge of a topic exists, thinking is ‘novice’, and thus it is likely that a concept will be misinterpreted or only partially understood. In contrast, the expert thinker has a great deal of knowledge of a topic, and thus sophisticated understanding exists. Crucially though, Carey argued that both children and adults are capable of ‘novice’ and ‘expert’ levels of understanding simultaneously, depending on how much they know about a particular topic.

For example, Carey cites 3-year-old dinosaur ‘experts’ who can tell you not only the names of all the dinosaurs but their eating habits, habitat, chronology and relative size. She similarly recognises young computer experts and chess players. Equally possible is novice thinking by adults when learning about a new topic for the first time, as evidenced for example by game-show contestants attempting to draw their internal anatomy! Thus, Carey argues that whilst children are far more likely to be ‘novice’ thinkers on a range of topics because their overall knowledge level is inevitably less, there is nothing about childhood thinking per se that limits children’s understanding. Consequently a child as young as three may well be able to develop a sophisticated understanding of a topic provided the knowledge is imparted at an accessible level and pace.

What emerges when comparing Piaget’s nativist perspective and Carey’s empirical perspective is a polarity between their two views, which regard either maturation or learning as very much the dominant forces in child development. It is the interactionist perspective, however, that offers the possibility of bridging this nature–nurture gap. Thus the theories of Lev Vygotsky (1896–1934) perhaps offer the most useful tool for healthcare practitioners in seeking developmental theory to underpin their practice (Daly et al 2008, Holaday et al., 1994, Rushforth, 1999 and Shayer, 2003).


Vygotsky and the ‘zone of proximal development’


Vygotsky (1978) was working in Russia at a similar time to Piaget, but his early death (aged just 38) and delayed translation of his work hindered his wider recognition for many years. Importantly, unlike Carey, his views were not in opposition to those of Piaget, and, indeed, more recent authors have argued that there are rather more similarities than differences in their work (Shayer 2003). Like Piaget, Vygotsky believed in the importance of maturation and biological processes but he saw the interplay between these processes and the child’s social world as being of prime importance. He saw thought processes as uniquely human and derived from children’s early exposure to language, and from social and cultural influences conveyed to the child by both family and teachers. Indeed, the nature of the role of ‘the teacher’ is perhaps one of the key differences between Piagetian and Vygotiskian perspectives.

Central to Vygotsky’s work was his notion of the ‘zone of proximal development’, which he defined as:

The distance between the actual developmental level as determined by independent problem solving and the level of potential development as determined through problem solving under adult guidance or in collaboration with more capable peers




Translating Vygotskian perspectives into practice


The significance of Vygotsky’s perspective in contrast to Piaget’s is considerable because it offers the possibility of enhancing and accelerating the child’s development by teaching. Unlike Carey, Vygotsky felt there were maturational limits on how far a child’s understanding could develop at a given point in time. However, although these limits are in many ways congruent with the stages Piaget describes, in Vygotsky’s theories the child can achieve understanding at a far earlier age than Piaget would suggest. Thus Vygotsky’s theory offers teachers and health practitioners the possibility of considerably enhancing children’s understanding through education.

Thus if a Vygotskian perspective rather than a Piagetian perspective influences our healthcare practice, the key difference is that a child’s developmental potential is not persistently viewed in negative terms but rather in positive ones. Piagetian ‘tools to guide practice’ are framed in terms of what children are unable to understand (e.g. Taylor et al 1999 p 64). By contrast, a Vygotskian perspective encourages the practitioner to find out what the child already knows and then to use this as a basis for working with the child and family to help the child to reach an enhanced level of understanding (Gaffney, 2000, Holaday et al., 1994 and Rushforth, 1999).

Vygotsky’s work was further developed by Bruner (1972), who used the analogous term ‘scaffolding’ to describe the role of teachers (both professionals and parents) within the ‘zone of proximal development’. Bruner saw this human scaffolding as a ‘supportive mechanism’, which was gradually withdrawn as the child strengthens in his or her own knowledge and understanding. Bruner believed that any topic could be meaningfully conveyed at some level to any child, provided it was appropriately individualised and congruent with what the child already knew and understood.

B9780702031830100116/reflect.jpg is missingReflect on your practice



Case study: Vygotskian perspectives


Consider again Jack, the 5-year-old child admitted to hospital described earlier. Now reconsider his care from a Vygotskian perspective:


• What differences emerge when compared with the earlier Piagetian perspective?


• Which approach to Jack’s care are you more comfortable with and why?


Children’s conceptualisation of health, illness and their internal bodies


One example of applying cognitive developmental theory to practice is consideration of the ways in which children conceptualise health and illness concepts. The ways in which we interpret children’s abilities in this domain has considerable potential to influence the quality of care they receive, their understanding of their illness and treatment, and the extent to which they can be actively involved in decisions pertaining to their care. A summary is offered here; for a more detailed consideration of this area see Bibace and Walsh, 1981 and Rushforth, 1999 and Siegal & Peterson (1999).

Since the middle part of the 20th century, numerous authors have researched children’s ability to understand the concepts of health, illness and their internal bodies. The early 1960s through to the mid-1980s saw the publication of numerous studies suggesting that children’s understanding of these concepts increased with age. Many studies also offered clear links with Piagetian theory, arguing the inevitability of the many misconceptions displayed by the younger children within the studies. However, the seminal work within the field was arguably that of Bibace and Walsh, 1980 and Bibace and Walsh, 1981, who offered a stage theory of children’s conceptualisation of illness that was very closely aligned to Piaget’s earlier described stage theory of cognitive development. Thus preoperational children (aged 2–7) were seen as having an illogical or magical understanding of illness, and concrete operational children (aged 7–11) were seen as having a limited and largely external understanding with little awareness of internal biological processes. It was only the formal operational child (aged 11+) who was viewed as likely to have any detailed understanding of illness physiology (see Vacik et al 2001 for a fuller summary).

A similar stage theory was also published by Perrin & Gerrity (1981). The title of this study, ‘There’s a demon in my belly’ (actually the child had been told he had oedema) clearly conveyed the typical misconceptions of younger children. Like Bibace and Walsh, 1980 and Bibace and Walsh, 1981 before them, Perrin & Gerrity (1981) argued that such misunderstandings are an inevitably consequence of cognitive immaturity.

However, the later 1980s and 1990s saw a gradual turning point within the literature. A growing body of authors recognised that such studies, although offering useful tools in terms of understanding the way in which children conceptualise health and illness, were also misrepresenting younger children’s potential to gain enhanced understanding of these health and illness concepts.

As early as 1980, and many years ahead of their peers, Kister & Patterson (1980) noticed that children who better understood ‘contagion’ were less likely to display ‘imminent justice explanations’ (the belief that illness was a punishment). Thus for the first time they acknowledged that enhancing understanding had the potential to reduce children’s fears and misconceptions.

Also of interest at this time was the work of Burbach & Peterson (1986), who offered the first systematic review of the earlier literature, and again criticised the Piagetian dominance within the earlier work. Similarly Eiser (1989), a prominent UK researcher in the field, challenged the Piagetian dominance in her own earlier work and suggested the earlier discussed theory of Carey (1985) as an important alternative perspective.

One of the most important studies at this time was the work of Vessey (1988), who tested children’s knowledge of their internal anatomy before and after instruction. She was thus the first author to clearly demonstrate the potential for children to achieve enhanced understanding of their internal bodies in response to instruction. Many other authors from this era also carried out studies that demonstrated children’s greater understanding of health and illness concepts. These included Bird and Podmore, 1990 and Hergenrather and Rabinowitz, 1991 and Longsdon (1991). It is important to state that these authors did not dismiss Piaget’s theories outright, but they certainly challenged his assertions that children’s potential to understand was limited by their maturation. All offered evidence of children demonstrating far more sophisticated levels of understanding than Piaget had previously given them credit for.

In reviewing these more recent studies, it is easy to see the parallels with Vygotsky’s work, although it was only in Holaday et al’s 1994 paper that this link was first explored explicitly. Subsequently, around the turn of the century, many authors offered studies that demonstrate considerable understanding of health, illness and internal anatomy by even very young children (Elliott and Watson, 2000, Gaffney, 2000, Gaudion, 1997, McEwing, 1996, McGrath and Huff, 2001, Schmidt, 2001, Williams and Binnie, 2002 and Yoos, 1994

Only gold members can continue reading. Log In or Register to continue

Stay updated, free articles. Join our Telegram channel

Jun 15, 2016 | Posted by in NURSING | Comments Off on The dynamic child

Full access? Get Clinical Tree

Get Clinical Tree app for offline access