Ethics in Perianesthesia Nursing

section epub:type=”chapter” id=”c0040″ role=”doc-chapter”>



Understanding ethics


Understanding the nature of ethical reflection requires the establishment of a common language and definition of terms. What do we mean when we use the terms ethics and morality? What is the nature of a moral dilemma? How can we know which rules, principles, standards, or guidelines are best for determining appropriate ethical behavior in the resolution of everyday dilemmas?


The terms ethics and morality, while related, remain distinct. Ethics is derived from the Greek root ethos, meaning “character.”1Morality or morals is derived from the Latin word mores or moralis, meaning “customs, character, or habit.”1 The ancient terms have a shared meaning. Today, persons engaged in the formal discipline of ethical reflection have a more distinct understanding. Beauchamp and Childress2 understand ethics as a “generic term for various ways of understanding and examining the moral life” and morality as “norms about right or wrong human conduct that are so widely shared that they form a stable (although usually incomplete) social consensus.” Morality informs persons in society as to what behavior or conduct may be considered good or right. How one should act in a given situation describes a moral question.


Ethics is the formal analysis, study, and reflection on how individuals answer basic questions of moral behavior. Ethics asks the question: How do I justify my actions, and what reasons, rules, principles, standards, or guidelines should direct my decisions? Ethics is understood as a formal discipline engaged in the systematic assessment of the morals that exist in the lives of individuals and society. The goal of ethical reflection, particularly in health care, has the practical function of assisting individuals or groups in the resolution of moral dilemmas. A dilemma occurs when one is faced with a choice between two or more equally desirable but mutually exclusive options. A moral dilemma is present when a moral obligation exists on both sides of the choice—to either perform or refrain from performing an action—and ethical reasons can be found to support either of the alternatives.3 The essence of a moral dilemma is conflict. That is, a moral dilemma occurs when an individual or society experiences a conflict between competing values, duties, and obligations in a given situation.


A classic example of a moral dilemma that continues to evade resolution in American society is abortion. Supporters of “choice” rights give greater weight to the moral status of the woman as an independent and autonomous agent. Those in opposition argue that the fetus is a human being with its own independent moral status deserving of protection. One cannot equally honor both sets of values or obligations. This simplified version of the abortion debate illustrates the conflict of competing values inherent in any moral dilemma.


Definitions


Autonomy The right to determine what happens to one’s own body, choosing treatment options consistent with one’s values.


Confidentiality Personal promise and trust that information about a patient’s health and treatment will be used only for the patient’s benefit and with care team members on a “need to know” basis.


Ethics Formal analysis, study, and reflection on questions of moral behavior; systematic reflection on the “ought.”


Informed Consent Detailed process of communication between a patient and physician regarding authorization for a particular medical intervention, including clear understanding of its benefits, risks, and alternatives.


Privacy Patient’s right to control access and distribution of personal information regarding his or her health and treatment; respect for patient’s personal space to ensure dignified care.


Required Reconsideration Comprehensive conversation between providers and patient/surrogate regarding a patient’s do-not-resuscitate (DNR) status during the administration of anesthesia.


The emergence of bioethics


Ethical reflection can apply to any arena of life, but in the past four decades, a new term has come to signify ethical reflection in the health care field: bioethics, or more precisely biomedical ethics. Bioethics is the application of ethical study and reflection to the life sciences. The term clinical ethics has been used to define ethical reflection in the clinical context of the actual care of patients. Many of the ethical concerns that confront professionals in the perianesthesia context are, by nature, clinical ethics issues.


The emergence of bioethics as a field within health care responds to a series of emerging problems in the second half of the 20th century. This period represents a time in American history of social fomentation related to developing individual and civil rights concerns, to the recognition that society has become increasingly pluralistic, and to the rapid development of technologic advances in medicine. Each of these concurrent historic forces led to novel moral challenges and the need for new ways to address the transformative dilemmas. For years, medical ethics remained under the purview of physicians who almost exclusively governed decision making for patients. Discussion or reflection on difficult moral problems encountered in the delivery of care or in medical research was kept private. After 1950, a number of noteworthy medical and legal cases emerged in the context of a rapidly changing society, which led to challenges to paternalism and gave rise to bioethics as a new interdisciplinary discipline. David Rothman4 describes this historic development as one in which physicians slowly became “strangers at the bedside” as other professions more frequently weighed in on the deliberations of medical decision making and recurring ethical dilemmas.


Isolation occurred in part because paternalistic ways of governing health care by physicians began to break down in the face of increasing social challenges. Physicians no longer maintained sole discretion in addressing problems and shaping policy. Individuals from the fields of philosophy, religion, law, journalism, nursing, and the social sciences began to pay attention to issues in health care and began to organize to address their concerns. A more informed citizenry began to demand a more active voice in decision making and oversight in the delivery of medical care.


Paradigmatic cases


The development of bioethics has been fueled by noteworthy medical and legal cases. These cases are significant for leading to profound changes in the way similar and future medical cases would be viewed. They reshaped health policy and law and reformed ethical practices in the way other patients in similar circumstances would be treated. The cases led to a different way of perceiving and valuing the moral obligations owed to patients by physicians, researchers, and other health care professionals.


Human Subjects Research


Among the most sweeping reform in the second half of the 20th century was in the arena of medical research with human subjects. For much of medicine’s history, the improvement of care for patients has been through the trial-and-error method of experimentation. Few therapies, when initially applied, had any guarantee of success, and some were fraught with the risk of further injury or debilitation to the patient. Early medical researchers were practicing physicians whose small-scale experiments were conducted solely for therapeutic benefit. The goal of experimentation was undertaken not as much to benefit future patients as to heal the very individual under the immediate care of the practicing physician.5 Most research was, at least in its intent, benevolent and humanistic, with the Hippocratic ideal of “doing no harm” providing the guiding norm of the experimenter’s conduct. Nonetheless, two key events revealed how flagrantly this norm can be ignored when the focus shifts to utilitarian goals rather than the safety and welfare of humans.


Nazi Germany, forever remembered for war crimes committed against humanity, was instrumental in perpetrating mass exterminations of innocent members of “undesirable” ethnic groups and other minorities. The techniques for these exterminations were perfected by Nazi physicians whose gruesome acts were later publicly revealed in the Nuremberg trials and documented by American observer Dr. Leo Alexander.6 The trials revealed how physicians and administrators conspired to engage in medical experiments such as forced sterilizations, poisonings, the infliction of simulated combat injuries, exposure to infections and extreme weather conditions, and ultimately the refinement of euthanasia techniques on those deemed mentally or physically “defective.” There were approximately 275,000 victims over a 10-year span of time. After these staggering revelations, an international tribunal of judges developed what is known as the Nuremberg Code, a statement of 10 principles that govern the ethical conduct of medical experimentation with human subjects. At the heart of the code is that the “voluntary consent of the human subject is absolutely essential” and that freedom from coercion, force, duress, or deception is a condition of participation in any form of experimentation. Expanding the moral framework for the conduct of medical research in the Nuremberg Code, the World Medical Association adopted the Helsinki Declaration in 1964.


Unfortunately, the efforts of Nuremberg and Helsinki did not end the problems with human research. Within the United States, these important principles did not filter into the conduct of physician experimenters, which became all too apparent in the infamous research project known as the Tuskegee Syphilis Study. From 1932 to 1972, the U.S. Public Health Service (USPHS), later known as the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC), engaged in a research study that involved 400 African American men in Macon County, Alabama. What began as a small time-limited project to improve the treatment of syphilis among poor minorities expanded into a full-blown plan marked by deception and discrimination that yielded no new information about the disease and offered no bona fide treatment for subjects.7 Initiated with hopes of understanding the disease and finding the definitive cure, the study evolved into an observation of how the disease progressed through its various stages, often culminating in death.


Participants in the study were led to believe that they were being provided treatment for what the physician researchers called bad blood, a euphemistic term for any kind of blood-related condition. Treatment amounted essentially to various placebos combined with painful nontherapeutic spinal taps. Subjects were induced to participate in the study through the offer of free treatment, meals, and transportation. Free burial insurance was promised on the condition the research subjects permit an autopsy upon their deaths for documentation of the effects of the end stages of the disease. Even when the curative antibiotic of penicillin became widely available, subjects of the study were prohibited from receiving it so researchers might continue to track the disease’s effects on the unsuspecting subjects’ bodies. The deception and coercion continued until USPHS investigator Peter Buxtun learned of the project from a colleague. Frustrated in his attempts to end the study by working within the USPHS, Buxtun turned to the press, and reporter Jean Heller broke the story in July 1972.8


The public and political outcry that followed the revelation of the study culminated in its immediate suspension and congressional passage of the Federal Research Act of 1974, which created two significant entities.9 First, the act established what is now known as the Office for Human Research Protections, which mandates that all institutions receiving federal funding for research with human subjects maintain institutional review boards with oversight for the safety and ethical treatment of research subjects. Second, the act established the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. The multi-profession commission was assigned to craft guidelines that would serve as a moral foundation for future human research regulation.5 By 1979, the commission had arrived at a policy statement known as the Belmont Report.10 The report highlighted three basic ethical principles that guide all medical research involving humans in the United States. The principle of respect for persons requires that participation in research be based on the voluntary informed consent of the subject of the study. The principle of beneficence calls for a comprehensive risk and benefit assessment that weighs the potential harm against the potential benefit to the current subjects or future patients. The principle of justice requires that research subjects be chosen equitably and that a fundamental fairness in both benefits gained and risks incurred be shared by research participants. Justice also requires that the more vulnerable members of society, such as children, prisoners, pregnant women, and the mentally challenged, be given added protection in research.


Reforms and regulations that emerged from Tuskegee and the Belmont Report now ensure that essential elements are present in medical or behavioral research studies that involve persons. These elements are voluntary participation, informed consent, comprehension by the subject of the nature and purpose of the study, full disclosure of risks and benefits, disclosure of alternatives to participation in research, and the option to withdraw from the study without penalty.


End-of-Life Cases


Controversial patient care cases involving end-of-life decisions hold a prominent place in the development of the bioethics movement. Three cases are particularly noteworthy; all involved young women, each of whom was severely incapacitated and unable to participate in decisions regarding life-sustaining treatment. The first landmark case is that of Karen Ann Quinlan. Karen Ann was a 21-year-old woman who suffered an anoxic brain injury as a result of an overdose. She never regained consciousness and was sustained by a ventilator and feeding tube. Eventually she was given a diagnosis of a persistent vegetative state (PVS), a neurological condition in which she was believed to have no awareness of herself, others, or her surroundings. After some months Karen Ann’s parents, following what they believed would be her own wishes, asked the physicians caring for her to remove the ventilator and allow a natural death. The physicians refused, thus setting the stage for a legal battle that eventually landed before the New Jersey Supreme Court. The court ruled in the favor of Karen Ann’s parents on the basis that Karen Ann had a fundamental right to privacy including the right not to receive treatment against her will.11


Remarkably, Karen Ann lived another 10 years after the removal of the ventilator while being sustained on the feeding tube. She died in 1986.


The second case involved Nancy Cruzan, a 24-year-old woman who also suffered a severe anoxic brain injury as a result of an auto accident in 1983. Like Karen Ann, she was eventually determined to be in a PVS. Nancy was not ventilator dependent but did have a gastrostomy tube for feeding and hydration. Four years after her injury, Nancy’s parents asked her physicians to remove the feeding tube as Nancy had previously stated that she would not want to be artificially kept alive if she could not be “at least halfway normal.”12 Her physicians and the state of Missouri opposed, leading to what has been referred to as the first “right to die” case to go before the U.S. Supreme Court. The court issued its ruling in June 1990 in which it acknowledged an individual’s right to refuse treatment, even life-sustaining feeding tubes. Yet the court also said that states could require “clear and convincing” evidence that such refusal was made when that person was still competent. Further clarifying evidence of Nancy’s wishes emerged later, leading to the withdrawal of the feeding tube. Nancy died in December 1990.


The Cruzan case and the memory of the Quinlan case before it propelled the creation of federal legislation designed for individuals to state their desire to refuse life-sustaining treatment under the conditions set forth by the Supreme Court even without capacity and the ability to communicate. The Patient Self-Determination Act of 1990 established on a national level the legitimacy of previously written advance directives as valid legal expressions of an individual’s desire to limit or refuse treatment in end-of-life circumstances.13 These advance directives, often referred to as living wills (and. in many states, include durable power of attorney for health care decisions), in theory meet the “clear and convincing” evidence standard required by the U.S. Supreme Court. While all 50 states recognize and honor some form of written advance directives, problems persist in these difficult cases in both the interpretation of generalized written statements and the infrequency of their use among the public.14,15 Another attempt to assist patients, families, and clinicians in understanding a patient’s wishes for end-of-life care is found in the growing influence of the Physician Orders for Life-Sustaining Treatments (POLST) paradigm.16 POLST documents, intended for those with life-limiting or terminal disease processes, provide more specific guidance than generalized advance directives. POLST creates a specific set of medical orders by a physician based upon the expressed wishes and values of a patient. POLST is not a complete substitute for an advance directive. Rather, it builds upon and complements the wishes of the patient as expressed in an advance directive.


The case of Terri Schiavo is yet another tragic end-of-life case complicated by the absence of an advance medical directive and the lack of clear communication and understanding among family members over end-of-life wishes.17,18 Like Quinlan and Cruzan before her, Terri suffered an anoxic injury from a cardiac arrest that rendered her a total care patient in a PVS for 15 years. Terri was kept alive by a gastrostomy tube. Initially Terri’s husband, Michael, and her parents, Bob and Mary Schindler, were united in their efforts to keep Terri alive in the hopes of her recovery. Over time, however, Michael came to the conclusion that Terri would not recover and sought to remove the feeding tube. Terri’s parents, deeply religious, opposed. The disagreement between them led to a bitter and international public dispute waged in the courts for more than a decade. A lower court found in favor of Michael with the U.S. Supreme Court refusing to hear the case on three separate occasions, each time affirming the appropriateness of the lower court findings. In the end, the gastrostomy tube was removed and Terri died in March 2005. The official cause of death by the medical examiner was listed as “complications from anoxic encephalopathy.”19


The cases of Quinlan, Cruzan, and Schiavo reveal the ongoing struggle clinicians and families face in making decisions on behalf of patients with incapacitated conditions. The legacy of these cases highlights the continuing difficulties in withdrawing or withholding treatment in the care of patients with life-threatening conditions and little or no hope of recovery. Even the closest of kin can sometimes be unclear about what their loved ones would desire in critical cases.20


Proponents of the principle of autonomy drive yet another option for end-of-life decision making, physician-assisted death (PAD) or physician-assisted suicide (PAS). Oregon was the first state to legalize this option through its Death with Dignity Act passed in 1997. The Death with Dignity Act “allows terminally ill Oregonians to end their lives through the voluntary self-administration of lethal medications, expressly prescribed by a physician for that purpose.”21 Since then, seven other states have legalized PAD (Washington, Vermont, California, Hawaii, Maine, New Jersey, and Colorado by legislation; Montana by court ruling). The passage of the California statute was significantly influenced by the case of Brittany Manyard, a young California woman diagnosed with terminal brain cancer who moved to Oregon to have the option for PAD that was not available in her home state.22 She died in 2014 at the age of 29 years with her husband and mother by her side after ingesting a lethal medication provided to her by an Oregon physician. Her personal public appeal spurred California legislators and Governor Jerry Brown to enact the law.23


Guiding principles


With insight gained from the history of research with human subjects and difficult end-of-life cases, a consensus has emerged on a set of guiding principles to assist health care professionals in the wide variety of clinical situations they may encounter. Beauchamp and Childress2 advance the clearest interpretation of these principles emerging over time from the common morality of society and the particular context of the clinical environment. These principles are respect for autonomy, nonmaleficence, beneficence, and justice.


Respect for autonomy refers to the norm of respect for the decision-making capacity of autonomous individuals. Defined as self-rule, autonomy means that competent adults have the fundamental right to determine what happens to their bodies and to make choices in treatment options consistent with their own beliefs and values.2 Autonomy is grounded in respect for persons and the inherent dignity and worth of each individual and is reflected in the Code of Ethics of the American Nurses Association.24 In the clinical setting, the autonomy of the patient is often challenged by the vulnerabilities created by pain, sedative effects, and severe illness as well as the anxiety produced by a lack of understanding of the complexities of the modern health care institution such as the medical language used by professionals. The obligation of clinical caregivers is to uphold autonomy by engaging in an ongoing process of informed consent, maintaining privacy and confidentiality, and enhancing, to the greatest degree possible, the mental and emotional capacity of the patient in his or her decision making. In the American context, autonomy is often thought of as the first and most important of the four principles.


Nonmaleficence refers to the obligation of clinicians to prevent harm to patients under their care or to minimize risks of harm to the fullest extent possible. This norm is often linked to the medical framework of the Hippocratic admonition primum non nocere, translated to mean “above all, do no harm.”2 The potential for harm to patients in health care can be understood in both broad and narrow terms. Nursing frames this understanding in the ethical obligation to advocate for processes that minimize harm and maximize comfort and support for patients.24 Nonmaleficence refers to the effort made by clinicians to limit physical pain, disability, or even death as a consequence of the treatment process itself. More broadly, the term refers to the duty to alleviate the emotional and spiritual suffering of the patient undergoing the traumatic experience of illness, institutionalization, isolation, and loss.


Beneficence is the principle that speaks to the duty of promoting the ultimate welfare of the patient above all other concerns. In common usage, beneficence speaks to acts of mercy, kindness, and charity.2 As such, beneficence and nonmaleficence may be thought of as two sides of the same coin. Nonmaleficence emphasizes not harming the patient in the effort to do good; beneficence supports doing good for the patient. Again, the obligation to serve as a patient advocate in a manner that promotes health, well-being, and especially safety is a component of sound ethical practice for the nursing professional. In health care, beneficence speaks to the humanitarian values that should underlie decision making and treatments offered to vulnerable persons. It is no accident that the word hospital is associated with the term hospitality. Beneficence affirms that patients should be treated as valued guests in what can often be a foreboding institutional environment. It also suggests that, although clinicians often are tempted by interests in conflict with the patient’s welfare, they should seek to set aside those interests or minimize their effects as much as possible to maintain professional integrity.


The last and perhaps most elusive principle promoted is the principle of justice. The elusiveness of justice is the result of the wide variety of ways it is defined and understood in society. Within the context of health care, justice is best understood as the obligation of clinicians to fairly distribute the medical benefits, risks, and costs associated with the provision of health care.2 As such, persons in similar circumstances are to be treated similarly. The challenges to the fairness principle are immeasurable in the modern American health care system. Global challenges are most prominent with respect to health disparities and visible in the debates concerning universal health insurance, equity of access, and financing the health care industry. Clinical challenges to justice are more evident in the struggle to evenly allocate scarce resources such as organs for transplant and blood products as well as access to care, services, and beds in emergency and critical care areas. Justice for the practicing nurse might be understood again in terms of advocacy, this time in the promotion of equality in the provision of quality care through the use of appropriate standards of practice for all patients.24


Perianesthesia ethics


Nursing professionals face a complex maze of ethical issues within the perioperative context. The intensity of a fast-paced environment with limited room for error demands not only clinical competence but also critical thinking, quick judgment, and clear communication. Vigilance regarding professional functioning and ethical practice is essential for the achievement of positive clinical outcomes within a morally sound arena. Although many issues exist, the ethical issues faced by perianesthesia nurses can be captured within four general categories that underscore professional behavior and function: (1) informed consent, (2) privacy and confidentiality, (3) civility, and (4) patient safety.


Informed Consent


Informed consent is the process of communication between a patient and physician that results in the authorization or understanding for a specific medical intervention.25 Informed consent is rooted in respect for persons, patient autonomy, and self-determination and formalizes a component of the covenant between the patient and the physician. It is built on the principles of trust and truth-telling regarding the use of a particular intervention or treatment to achieve a desired medical outcome. Informed consent stands on the practice of shared decision making, a building block to active participation by the patient.26


Despite the clarity of definition for the informed consent process, multiple questions or potential ethical conflicts can arise for nursing staff within the perioperative period. A simple question such as “What were they going to do again?” asked by an anxious patient in the preoperative holding area can set off a series of internal alarms in the mind of a nurse. Does the patient need reassurance or more information? Is it a momentary failure of memory or a lack of adequate understanding of the procedure that prompted the question? Who secured the consent of the patient? How was the request approach conducted? How does the nurse understand the professional and ethical obligations in the face of a seemingly unsure patient and the pressure of a tight operating room (OR) schedule?


The nurse might begin by seeking verification of a signed written consent form. Whereas the presence of the form might satisfy the technical act of granting consent, it may or may not fulfill the ethical obligation. Informed consent is more than a means of securing a signature. Rather, it is a process of open, two-way communication that implies full disclosure and provides detailed information on the nature of a specific procedure. A comprehensive informed consent process not only reviews the diagnosis and purpose of the intervention but also outlines its potential risks and benefits. It includes alternative treatment options, if any, and the risks and benefits of forgoing the treatment procedure. Informed consent assumes that the threshold elements of patient capacity and voluntary nature are met.27,28 Research conducted during the perianesthesia phase of care should likewise follow ethical, professional, and legal guidelines, a potentially ethical challenge for the nurse with the dual role of provider and research collaborator.29


Questions may also arise regarding the duration and scope of a signed informed consent. Could the signature in the previous scenario been from a posture of haste and convenience, making it more implied than informed? Could it have been secured appropriately but over 90 days prior to surgery? Should the consent still be valid for the patient who is now unsure about the nature of the procedure? Is the timing of the consent still valid? What is the nurse’s understanding of the consent process and obligation to confirm that the patient now understands the potential benefits, risks, and surgical outcomes?30


Informed consent requires that the process be completed by a clinician able to provide the intervention and in a manner that allows time and space for patients to ask questions, seek clarification, and discuss potential options for care. This includes consents for anesthesia, which should include the type of anesthesia (e.g., general, monitored anesthesia care, regional, IV sedation, or other modality). All benefits, risks, and alternatives should be discussed, and a mutually agreeable plan of care should be documented and communicated to the care team. An adequate informed consent process is further challenged by potential language barriers such as complex medical terminology, cultural diversity, and functional limitations among populations with cognitive impairments.31,32 All these issues underscore the significance of effective communication in the patient–physician relationship and among members of the interdisciplinary team.


What, then, is the ethical responsibility of the nurse in the holding area faced with the patient’s question of uncertainty and the surgical team’s schedule? To what extent is the nurse’s ethical obligation to serve as a patient advocate in support of an informed decision? How might the nurse’s obligation be affected for the patient who adds the statement, “At least my surgeon promised to be there for the entire operation,” when the nurse knows of that particular surgeon’s tendency toward intermittent presence while residents perform most operations? What if the nurse understood from a colleague that the patient’s original consent was provided under pressure to comply? Specific questions such as these identify just a few of the immediate moral dilemmas that have implications for clinical practice and patient outcomes.


Resuscitation in the Perioperative Context


A special circumstance of informed consent in the perioperative context is the issue of resuscitation for patients with an advance directive, specifically with a documented DNR (or DNAR) order. Cardiopulmonary resuscitation (CPR) is the only medical procedure routinely performed in a hospital without the expressed consent of a patient. Routine management of the patient under the influence of anesthesia shares some of the same interventions and characteristics of resuscitation. As such, the practice of routine suspension of DNR orders for patients during anesthesia care in the OR was commonly accepted through the 1980s.


By the mid-1990s, the evolution of increased respect for patient autonomy evolved from changes in medical practice and the Patient Self-Determination Act of 1990. Respect for patient autonomy and concern for adequate informed consent procedures challenged old practices and forced the issue onto the agendas of key professional organizations. Emerging from these conversations was support for the practice of required reconsideration. A comprehensive conversation regarding a patient’s DNR status during the administration of anesthesia is recommended between the physician and the patient or surrogate, with the result documented and communicated among health care team members. Anything less is a violation of a patient’s right to self-determination and fails adherence to the principle of patient autonomy.3341 This position has obvious ethical implications for providers. A comprehensive conversation requires intentional dialogue with patients or surrogates regarding the options and implications of maintaining or suspending the DNR order during surgery. Required reconsideration has since become the predominant recommended approach supported by the American Society of PeriAnesthesia Nurses, the American College of Surgeons, the American Society of Anesthesiologists, the Association of periOperative Registered Nurses, the American Association of Nurse Anesthetists, and the American Academy of Nursing.4247


Despite the consensus movement toward required reconsideration, institutional culture regarding the application of this practice persists along with opinions among anesthesiologists, surgeons, nurse anesthetists, perianesthesia nurses, and patients.48 Variation in practice among providers is reflective of the complications associated with the delivery of anesthesia and the ability to differentiate between an arrest caused by sedation as opposed to the progression of disease.36,49 Additional complications are associated with inadequate familiarity with current guidelines on advance directives in the perioperative setting.50


Organizational policies can mandate such communication and documentation of the conversation, but the ethical challenge to informed consent remains in the details. Recent studies suggest that, despite established policy, compliance with detailed documentation of patient preferences remains mixed.5153 Informed consent regarding the suspension of a DNR order implies that patients or surrogates are offered information about their procedures, including potential risks and benefits, alternative treatment, and the potential implications of forgoing the intervention. Careful consideration of the individuality of each patient is critical. Discussion of how resuscitation would be managed in the perioperative period is an essential but complicated discussion. Conversation within this context should be conducted without coercion in a language understandable to patients or surrogates and with sufficient time to allow questions and answering concerns to lead to an informed decision. The nature of the preoperative conversation is particularly critical to avoid assumed contractual buy-in to postoperative life support, especially for DNR patients facing high-risk surgery.54


Clear and consistent communication alone does not readily resolve the complexities of the management of a DNR order in the perioperative period. Discussion in the literature on the pragmatics of managing the DNR order in the perioperative period is reflected in two approaches, both supporting the ethical obligation to respect patient autonomy.55 One position suggests a means- or procedure-directed approach that examines routine resuscitative actions and determines which interventions would be offered in the perioperative period. The second position supports an ends-oriented approach that examines the goals of the patient relative to the present procedure. Both options suggest a limited resuscitation approach during the perioperative period as distinct from the two extreme options of suspension of DNR orders with unrestrained resuscitative efforts or maintenance of current DNR orders limiting all interventions not immediately associated with routine anesthesia care.


The procedure-directed approach provides a checklist of specific provider interventions.55 The application of this approach requires consideration of each optional intervention (i.e., those not associated with routine anesthesia care) individually between the patient or surrogate and the surgeon or anesthesia provider. The advantages of procedure-directed orders are the reduction of ambiguity and the consistency of application from one clinician to another throughout intraoperative resuscitation management. The limitations to procedure-directed orders include an expectation that anything but the most likely problems would be anticipated in advance and the limited flexibility offered the clinician in response to a temporary and readily reversible event.


The goal-oriented approach seeks to incorporate the patient’s values as the primary consideration in determination of the extent of resuscitation.55 Patients offer guidance regarding preferred outcomes but leave specific interventions to the discretion of the provider. Although this approach supports patient autonomy, it also provides a larger role for the provider. The advantage to this approach is that it offers flexibility to the clinician to act in accordance with a broad understanding of patient preferences should an unanticipated event occur in the OR setting. The limiting argument for this position has been that it risks putting unanticipated decision-making power back in the hands of the physician.


Keys to success for either of these approaches are communication and documentation. The complexity of this issue underscores the significant ethical obligations of the perioperative nurse. The obligation to act in the patient’s best interest demands that the nurse is knowledgeable and informed, beginning with having a clear understanding of the organization’s DNR policy and its specific application to the perianesthesia period. Equally important is that the nurse has knowledge of the DNR status of the patient during that period, including any documentation regarding limited resuscitation and knowledge of the time frame in the case of temporarily suspended DNR orders.


Autonomy and the COVID-19 Pandemic


While patient autonomy and informed consent remain the hallmark of shared decision making in the physician–patient relationship, the onset of the COVID-19 pandemic provided some potentially unique challenges to clinical ethics. Perhaps nowhere is this challenge more daunting than when it comes to limiting access to scarce resources such as ventilators that are critical to CPR. Inpatient resuscitation resulting in hospital discharge was already low, approximately 25%.56 Driven to develop guidelines on the use of scarce resources such as ventilators, hospitals were challenged to further balance medical indications with patient preferences when it comes to interventions such as ventilator access and resuscitation. The question then becomes at what point a public health crisis warrants limiting access to resources or a public health crisis risks a resurgence of physician paternalism.57 The necessary development of “crisis standards of care” by informed and reliable professional societies assists in clinical decision making and the uniform application of appropriate ethical guidelines.58 Similar concerns of equity and fairness in the distribution of resources are raised with regard to the variety of COVID-19 vaccine allocation frameworks that have been proposed. Planners at the federal, state, and local levels are challenged by the task to ensure that those with the greatest need and those who historically have suffered inequities in access to health care services are not disadvantaged in the vaccine implementation process.59


Civility


A fundamental ethical responsibility for all health care providers is working to create an environment that promotes respect and collegiality. One classic example is ensuring the establishment of a culture of civility and safety in the OR.60 Take an instance of the surgeon who, throughout the induction, intubation, and line placement, criticized and mocked the anesthesia team with repeated phrases such as “How long is this going to take? I have several cases to get done today . . . could you amateurs call for a real anesthesia team?” Or the instance of the surgeon who, over the objections of OR staff, ordered them to prematurely “flip” rather than carefully reposition the patient, resulting in the displacement of the arterial and one intravenous lines, leading to pooling of blood on the floor. These type of examples may not be uncommon, but potentially under-reported as well.61 While the immediate ethical responsibility to report may lie with frontline staff in these instances, the responsibility to act and protect them clearly sits with management, even at the highest levels of an organization.


Privacy and Confidentiality


Maintaining the privacy and confidentiality of patients remains a challenge for health care organizations and clinicians. Privacy and confidentiality are complementary rather than synonymous concepts.62Privacy suggests that a patient has the right to control general access and distribution of personal information about his or her health and implies that boundaries that protect a patient’s personal space are respected within a clinical setting. Confidentiality relates to the personal trust that intimate information shared by a patient with a clinician is used only for the patient’s medical benefit. As such, information is shared with those members of the interdisciplinary team on a need-to-know basis. Information should be shared with third parties only with permission of the patient except in the cases of an identified surrogate for the patient who lacks decision-making capacity. Discussion and consent regarding release of information in this situation should be managed in the preoperative phase. The ethical responsibility to maintain privacy and confidentiality proceeds from the principle of respect for persons that promotes human dignity and maximizes patient control.62 This responsibility applies to the preoperative setting when marking surgical sites to ensure minimal exposure. It also applies to treatment of patients under the effects of anesthesia by eliminating and addressing derogatory or disrespectful behaviors or communications.6365


One of the most significant challenges to patient privacy during the perioperative period is the physical setting of the postanesthesia care unit (PACU). More often than not, the PACU is configured as a multipatient care area with only curtains for privacy. Private communications between patients and clinicians are subject to being overheard by other patients or even visitors. The literature continues to support increased visitation for patients in the PACU as a means of decreasing family anxiety.6668 Family-centered care responds to visitation preferences of families and significant others yet increases the potential to compromise privacy obligated to other patients. This potential ethical compromise can be mitigated through consistent policy and practice.69,70


Respect for confidentiality has been given renewed attention as a result of health care reform for nurses who care for young adults who are not minors yet remain on parental health insurance plans. Another conflict that may emerge stems from the rights of parents who wish to be present when a minor child awakens from surgery. Staff members not directly involved in the care of specific patients may encounter neighbors and friends recovering from surgery who would have preferred to remain unnoticed. In addition, the changing world of social media creates new challenges that can blur the line between personal and professional boundaries. What constitutes responsible use of social networks?71,72 Can nurses, for example, “friend” patients on Facebook or talk about a patient scenario even without identifying factors?


How does the PACU nurse observe multiple patients while ensuring privacy? The typical PACU nurse monitors more than one patient, thus exposing patients to potential violations of personal space in the interest of patient safety. An additional challenge to the nurse can be finding the appropriate way to respond to the physician who performs examinations without properly drawing the curtain or who engages in intimate conversations with patients without proper discretion as to volume and content.


Teaching hospitals carry additional potential dilemmas in maintenance of patient privacy. The parameters of what is ethically permissible or appropriate relative to observation or examination by students or others in training of patients who are anesthetized remains ethically ambiguous. Should examination itself, the type of examination, the number of students observing, the nature and extent of the consent process, or some combination of these factors drive the parameters of ethical appropriateness? Should informed consent include details regarding these parameters? What is the extent of ethical obligation on the perianesthesia nurse to speak up as a patient advocate?


The professional responsibility to maintain confidentiality and privacy is clearly required from the perianesthesia nurse. The exchange of privileged patient information should follow the organization’s policies on confidentiality and the code of ethical conduct of the appropriate professional organization, which would include at a minimum the sharing of information on a need-to-know basis and the proper collection of patient data for research purposes.


Patient Safety


The ethical responsibility for all clinicians and health care providers to act in the best interest of patients is no more evident than in the obligation to ensure patient safety. The significance of this obligation on perianesthesia nurses is both organizational and personal. Minimally, this obligation stems from the ethical principle of nonmaleficence. Organizational obligation includes responsibility to ensure that the environment is safe for patients. Critical to patient safety is the requirement that a clinician at any given point in the treatment process demonstrate appropriate competencies for the level of provided care. Competency implies possession of the knowledge, skills, attitudes, and behavior to deliver the appropriate level of care on a consistent basis.73 Clinicians are obligated to know and to function within the standard of care of their professional role and the professional standards of practice within their discipline.74 This responsibility can be particularly challenging for nurses in the PACU, an environment frequently characterized by overcrowding because of limited intensive care unit beds and staffing shortages and where nurses might be asked to provide care outside the unit’s scope.75


The principle of beneficence speaks to the perianesthesia nurse’s responsibility to a wide range of ethical obligations. Ethical dilemmas faced by clinicians can include how to respond to a colleague who appears impaired in some way, what to do regarding the reporting of a medical error, or how to respond to a situation in which a colleague is engaged in deceptive practice or illegal behavior—all situations that affect maintenance of a safe environment and adherence to ethical practice and organizational guidelines.


In the current climate of the country and the opioid crisis in the world, it becomes particularly important to address any concerns about possible impairment or suspected diversion of drugs that would threaten the safety of patients at a vulnerable context in the hospital. It becomes ethically incumbent on nursing leaders, charge nurses, or nursing peers to report any impairment, question of impairment, or any signs of diversion to the appropriate chain of command.76 Addressing the issue can also be done with understanding and help with the professionals involved since addiction is a significant medical condition. Such obligation extends to the benefit of the practitioner as well as there are programs specifically developed for health care professionals, many with state licensing boards.


The nurse is obligated to follow best practice processes and be proactive about eliminating errors. One example of proactive practice is calling a “time-out” prior to any procedure. If guidelines for anything from a nerve block to correct site surgery are not followed properly during the procedure, the nurse calls a time-out and stops the procedure until it is corrected.77,78 Time-out is the opportunity to adhere to safety. As the advocate for patients at a vulnerable time, the nurse should be empowered to speak up, and organizations should support those efforts.


The transfer of the patient from the OR to the PACU has the potential to introduce a number of ethical dilemmas related to patient safety. One common dilemma faced by the perianesthesia nurse in the PACU setting is the obligation to determine unintended intraoperative awareness. The responsibilities of the nurse in this instance can be multiple. The nurse must make an initial assessment with an interview of the patient who emerges from the influence of anesthesia to determine whether any recollection of events exists or whether the patient experienced pain during the surgical procedure. If the finding is affirmative, the nurse must then determine how to communicate the information. Clear documentation of the patient’s response and notification of the surgeon and the anesthesia provider are critical. Equally important is communication of the patient’s experience to the intensive care unit or floor nurse who will assume care for the patient and who can identify resource personnel who could be available to support the patient who has experienced such trauma. The ethical dilemma becomes more complicated should the perianesthesia nurse discover that a pattern of unintended intraoperative awareness emerges as the result of care by a specific anesthesia provider or surgeon.


The hand-off from the OR to the PACU can be complicated by the pressure of time. What essential information needs to be passed from the OR nurse or the nurse anesthetist to the PACU nurse? How should the transfer of a patient whose condition is marginally stable or one whose condition is hemodynamically stable but in pain be handled between the nurse anesthetist and the PACU nurse? How could this situation be compromised by a demanding OR schedule that anticipates a speedy return to the OR by the anesthetist? Current literature supports the use of a structured process for hand-offs to ensure that all essential information is communicated. Many PACUs use the same structured process from anesthesia to PACU nurse and then PACU nurse to receiving nurse, allowing for consistency and safer continuity of care.79,80


Minimal responsibility in this instance includes documentation of the patient’s status upon arrival, information on the surgical and anesthesia course, and collaboration in the care of the patient until the PACU nurse accepts responsibilities. The proper medication management, particularly as it applies to pain in the postoperative period, remains a critical ethical obligation and can be a source of tension between the transferring anesthesia provider and the receiving PACU nurse. This process can be particularly complicated for the pediatric patient or the geriatric patient with cognitive impairment because clinicians may need knowledge and specialized training for such populations. Again, standardization of procedures and proper communication skills are key factors in successful patient transfers and outcomes.81 See Chapter 26 for more information about transition from the OR to the PACU.


Many organizations are implementing Enhanced Recovery after Surgery (ERAS) as an evidence-based standard protocol of care. ERAS is a multimodal perioperative care pathway designed to achieve early recovery for patients undergoing major surgery.82 ERAS starts at the inception of planning a surgical procedure and continues through discharge. The concepts of ERAS include patient optimization prior to surgery, reduction of infection, intraoperative fluid optimization and normothermia, reduced opioid use with implementation of multimodal pain plans, and early postoperative fluid intact and mobilization.83 Embedded in all aspects of a patient’s care, a team concept is inherent in its successful implementation and eventual improved patient outcomes.


Perioperative departments in many health care organizations have moved to team education and work on team dynamics to become successful in the full implementation of ERAS with surgical patients.84 Organizations have done so by establishing intense team education and engagement with skilled team dynamics educators, anesthesia, surgeons, ambulatory clinics, pre- and postoperative units, intraoperative nursing teams, and inpatient units; all of which have an impact on the success of the ERAS protocol and positive patient outcomes. Team training allows the team members to become comfortable with one another and learn how to determine how communication will occur, and should occur, with all team members. Communication is one of the guiding principles of team dynamics and, with the flow of the patient through the ERAS protocol, it is imperative that this occurs verbally and electronically for patient success.


A corollary of the ethical principle of respect for persons and the obligation to ensure patient safety is truth-telling. The ethical responsibility to tell the truth in medicine exists at both the organizational and individual patient levels. Organizationally, the perianesthesia nurse needs to determine the ethical course of action in disclosing potential safety problems under the pressure to move patients efficiently through the system. At an individual patient level, the perianesthesia nurse is challenged to determine the ethical course of action in facilitating disclosure of a medical error, even one seemingly inconsequential.8587


At one point or another, all health care professionals encounter a case that conflicts with their own personal value system or that creates significant emotional discomfort. Perianesthesia nurses are no different. Nursing professionals should make every effort to anticipate such potential conflicts in advance and refer to any organizational personnel policies that address this conflict. Generally speaking, refusal of anticipated conflicts of moral conscience is ethical provided no compromise to patient safety exists.


Resources for resolving ethical dilemmas


Clear and consistent communication between clinicians and patients as well as among clinicians continues to be the backbone of good ethical practice. Despite the most diligent practice, ethical dilemmas continue to challenge clinicians. The ethical responsibility for the perianesthesia nurse can become particularly burdensome in the perioperative environment, where issues of power and politics are never far away. Identification of resources to support staff seeking resolution of ethical conflicts can relieve the burden. Managers and supervisors should not be overlooked as resources for assistance. Supervisors should be dependable sources for accessing organizational policies or for support in dealing with colleagues in other disciplines. Staff access to organizational and departmental policies has been enhanced with the use of an institution’s intranet postings. In addition, the ethics codes for nearly all relevant professional nursing organizations are available through Internet websites. Questions regarding ethical practices related to release of patient information, business practices, or even professional behavior can be referred to ever-expanding corporate compliance programs.


Ethics Committees and Consultation Services


The Standards of The Joint Commission require that hospitals have an identifiable process for the resolution of ethical dilemmas. Subsequently, most hospital-established ethics committees are charged with three functions: the development of policies to address recurrent difficult situations such as end-of-life care orders; education within the organization that addresses issues faced by the organization or its specialty disciplines; and consultation with patients, families, and staff for the mediation of conflicts or exploration of treatment options. Although guidelines to determine the functioning of ethics committees can vary by organization, generally speaking, access to the ethics committee is available to any individual with standing in a case. This access includes patients or surrogates and staff involved in the care of the patient. Consultation services are generally provided by a subcommittee of the membership that possesses training in clinical ethics. Consultations, whether by the committee as a whole or by subcommittee, serve as nonbinding recommendations that identify the ethically appropriate care options available to the physician and patient.


Consultation provided by members of the ethics committee can be a critical resource. The goal of ethics consultation is the improvement of patient outcomes through a process of reasoned decision making. Consultation typically takes the form of facilitation and dialogue to ensure that the key ethical issues and the essential perspectives of persons with standing in a case are provided adequate voice. The value of ethics consultation is the availability and timely response of a neutral resource to assist staff in the exploration of ethically appropriate alternatives to a situation that lacks consensus. Like a medical consultation, an ethics consultation is a resource, not a final decision. Clarity on the purpose of a consultation is imperative so as not to disappoint clinicians who seek a quick resolution for a complex situation or an ally to advance a particular position.


Ethics Case Review Methodology


The use of a pragmatic tool to examine an ethical dilemma is a valuable resource for both the novice and the experienced clinician. Thoughtful case analysis requires a reasoned methodology, ensuring that a systematic approach is followed and that influential factors are given appropriate consideration. The use of a case-based methodology can facilitate responsible reflection with an objective theoretic framework while attending to the specifics of a particular situation. The following adaptation offers a pragmatic approach to moral problem solving.88,89



  • Assessment: What are the facts? What are the patient’s medical condition and prognosis? What are the needs of the patient (e.g., relief from suffering)? What are the current goals of treatment or care? What are the patient’s preferences? What is the patient’s capacity for decision making? For the patient who lacks capacity, have any care preferences been previously expressed or documented? If not, does the family/surrogate have an understanding of the patient’s values or what the patient would have wanted given the current medical condition? If not known, what are the family/surrogate preferences?
  • Moral Diagnosis: How are the ethical questions in the situation being framed by the participants who hold moral standing? Have all relevant persons been heard? Is the ethical dilemma clearly articulated? Separate facts from feelings. Clarify the points of disagreement or uncertainty. Identify and rank all relevant moral considerations. What ethical guidelines apply? Consider laws that may apply while carefully separating ethical from legal options during discussion. Are there similar cases in the literature that might be instructive? Identify and list the full range of morally acceptable options for resolving the case.
  • Goal Setting, Decision Making, and Plan Implementation: What options for resolution of the dilemma seem most appropriate and why? Do the goals of treatment or plan of care need to be revised? What resources can be brought to the situation for assistance? How would you negotiate a plan among the affected parties and achieve consensus on a plan? What would help resolve the conflict? Is consultation with the institutional ethics committee indicated? Is judicial review indicated? If so, consider consultation with risk management.
  • Evaluation: The implementation of any medical decision includes an element of ongoing evaluation. Consideration of the benefit of any intervention and the goals of treatment should be subject to periodic and regular review. Evaluation should include consideration of what could have been done to prevent the problem from occurring. Retrospective review might consider a range of issues from communication between providers and patient/family to assessment of institutional policy and practice.

Summary


Clinical ethics continues to develop into a mature field with established acceptance among health care professionals. Codes of professional ethics are the norm for nursing organizations, and there is a growing literature of ethical issues in perianesthesia nursing. Evolving technology and increased emphasis on patients’ rights presents ever-increasing options for care and considerations for decision making within the medical community. In addressing these issues, the perianesthesia nursing professional has much to contribute. It is crucial to develop the competencies and skills required to be effective clinicians who possess the critical assessment tools necessary to negotiate difficult situations in an environment of culturally diverse values.



References



  • 1American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language. ed 5 Houghton Mifflin Harcourt: Company; 2020.
  • 2 Beauchamp T.L., Childress J.F. Principles of biomedical ethics. ed 8 New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 2019.
  • 3 Fletcher J.C. Clinical ethics: History, content, and resources. In: Fletcher J.C., Lombardo P.A., Spencer E.M., eds. Fletcher’s introduction to clinical ethics. ed 3 Hagerstown, MD: University Publishing Group; 2005.
  • 4 Rothman D.J. Strangers at the bedside: a history of how law and bioethics transformed medical decision making. New York, NY: Basic Books; 1991.
  • 5 Jonsen A.R. The birth of bioethics. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 1998.
  • 6 Alexander L. Medical science under dictatorship. N Engl J Med. 1949;241:39–47.
  • 7 Jones J.H. Bad blood. New York, NY: The Free Press; 1993.
  • 8 Heller J. Syphilis victims in U.S. study went untreated for 40 years , NY Times. July 26, 1972.
  • 9 National Research Act of 1974, Pub. L. 93–348.
  • 10 The National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research: The Belmont report: ethical principles and guidelines for the protection of human subjects of research 1979. https://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/regulations-and-policy/belmont-report/read-the-belmont-report/index.html. Published 2018. Accessed January 27, 2021.
  • 11In the matter of Karen Quinlan, an alleged incompetent , 70 NJ 10, 355 A.2d 647. 1976.
  • 12Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Department of Health , 497 U.S. 261, 11 S. Ct. 2841. 1990.
  • 13Patient self-determination act of 1990, sections 4206 and 4751 of omnibus reconciliation act of 1990 , Pub. L. 101–508. November 5, 1990.
  • 14 Yadav K.N., Gabler N.B., Cooney E., Kent S., Kim J., Herbst N., Mante A., Halpern S.D., Courtright K.R. Approximately one in three US adults completes any type of advance directive for end-of-life care. Health Aff (Millwood). 2017;36:1244–1251.
  • 15 Bailoor K., Kamil L.H., Goldman E., Napiewocki L.M., Winiarski D., Vercler C.J., Shuman A.G. The voice is as mighty as the pen: integrating conversations into advance care planning. Bioethical Inquiry. 2018;15:184–191.
  • 16 POLST: Physician orders for life sustaining treatment. Published 2021. Accessed January 27, 2021.
  • 17 Gostin L.O. Ethics, the Constitution, and the dying process: The case of Theresa Marie Schiavo. JAMA. 2005;293:2403–2407.
  • 18 Wolfson J. Erring on the side of Theresa Schiavo: reflections of the special guardian ad litem. Hastings Cent Rep. 2005;35(3):16–19.
  • 19 Thogmartin J.R. Medical examiner, district six of the state of Florida: Report of autopsy for Schiavo. Theresa, case #505439 June 13, 2005.
  • 20 Spalding R. Accuracy in surrogate end-of-life medical decision-making: a critical review. Appl Psychol Health Well Being. 2020;doi:10.1111/aphw.1221.
  • 21 Oregon Public Health Division: The Oregon Death with Dignity Act. (website) https://www.oregon.gov/oha/ph/ProviderPartnerResources/Evaluationresearch/deathwithdignityact/Pages/index.aspx Accessed January 27, 2021.
  • 22 Manyard B. CNN Opinion: My right to die with dignity at 29. (website) cnn.com/2014/10/07/opinion/maynard-assisted-suicide-cancer-dignity. Accessed November 14, 2020.
  • 23 Lovett I., Perez-Pena R. California governor signs assisted suicide bill into law , NY Times. October 6, 2015.
  • 24 American Nurses Association: Code of ethics for nurses, 2015. (website) —http://nursingworld.org/practice-policy/nursing-excellence/ethics/code-of-ethics-for-nurses/ Accessed January 28, 2021.
  • 25 American Medical Association: Statement on Informed consent. www.ama-assn.org/delivering-care/ethics/informed-consent Accessed January 28, 2021.
  • 26 Chandrakantan A., Saunders D. Perioperative Ethical Issues. Anesthesiology Clin. 2016;34:35–42.
  • 27 Boyle R.S. The process of informed consent. In: Fletcher J.S., Lombardo P.A., Spencer E.M., eds. Fletcher’s introduction to clinical ethics. ed 3 Hagerstown, MD: University Publishing Group; 2005.
  • 28 Axson S.A., Giordano N.A., Hermann R.M., Ulrich C.M. Evaluating nurse understanding and participation in the informed consent process. Nurs Ethics. 2019;26(4):1050–1061.
  • 29 Larkin M.E., Beardslee B., Cagliero E., Griffith C.A., Milaszewski K., Mugford M.T., Myerson J.M., Ni W., Perry D.J., Winkler S., Witte E.R. Ethical challenges experienced by clinical research nurses: a qualitative study. Nurs Ethics. 2019;26(1):172–184.
  • 30 Akyuz E., Bulut H., Karadag M. Surgical nurses’ knowledge and practices about informed consent. Nurs Ethics. 2019;26(7-8):2170–2184.
  • 31 Grady C. Enduring and emerging challenges of informed consent. N Engl J Med. 2015;372(9):855–862.
  • 32 Silbert B.S., Scott D.A. Informed consent in patients with frailty syndrome. Anesth-Analg. 2020;130(6):1474–1481.
  • 33 Truog R.D. Do Not Resuscitate orders during anesthesia and surgery. Anesthesiology. 1991;74(3):606–608.
  • 34 Sumrall W.D., Mahanna E., Sabharwal V., Marshall T. Do not resuscitate, anesthesia, and perioperative care: a not so clear order. Ochsner J. 2016;16(2):176–179.
  • 35 Brown S.E.S., Antiel R.M., Blinman T.A., Shaw S., Neuman M.D., Feudter C. Pediatric perioperative DNR orders: a case series in a children’s hospital. J Pain Symp Manage. 2019;57(5):971–979.
  • 36 Hiestand D., Beaman M. Perioperative do not resuscitate suspension: the patient’s perspective. AORN J. 2019;109(3):326–334.
  • 37 Wada K., Szego M.J. Revisiting code status in patients undergoing GI endoscopy with a do-not-resuscitate order. Gastrointestinal Endoscopy. 2019;89(2):380–382.
  • 38 Chandrakantan A., Saunders T. Perioperative ethical issues. Anesthesiology Clin. 2016;34:35–42.
  • 39 Kalkman S., Lotty H., Meijerman J.M., Knape J.T.A., van Delden M. Survival after perioperative cardiopulmonary resuscitation: providing evidence base for ethical management of do-not-resuscitate orders. Anesthesiology. 2016;124(3):723–729.
  • 40 Hardin J., Forshier B. Adult perianesthesia do not resuscitate orders: a systematic review. J Perianesth Nurs. 2019;34(5):1054–1068.
  • 41 Shapiro M.E., Singer E.A. Perioperative advance directives: do not resuscitate in the operating room. Surg Clin N Am. 2019;99:859–865.
  • 42 American Association of Perianesthesia Nurses: A Position Statement on the Perianesthesia Patient with a Do-Not-Attempt-Resuscitation (DNAR) Advance Directive. https://www.aspan.org/Portals/6/docs/ClinicalPractice/PositionStatement/Current/PS_1.pdf?ver=2021-01-12-150828-490 . Published 2021. Accessed January 28, 2021.
  • 43 American College of Surgeons: Statement on advance directives by patients: “do not resuscitate” in the operating room. https://www.facs.org/about-acs/statements/19-advance-directives. Published 2014. Accessed January 28, 2021 (November 14, 2020).
  • 44 American Society of Anesthesiologists: Ethical guidelines for the anesthesia care of patients with do-not-resuscitate orders or other directives that limit treatment. (website) https://www.asahq.org/standards-and-guidelines/ethical-guidelines-for-the-anesthesia-care-of-patients-with-do-not-resuscitate-orders-or-other-directives-that-limit-treatment. Published 2018. Accessed January 28, 2021.
  • 45 Association of Operating Room Nurses: AORN position statement on perioperative care of patients with do-not-resuscitate or allow-natural-death orders. https://www.aorn.org/guidelines/clinical-resources/position-statements (February 6, 2021).
  • 46 American Association of Nurse Anesthetists: AANA position statements, advisory opinions, and considerations. (website) https://www.aana.com/docs/default-source/practice-aana-com-web-documents-(all)/reconsideration-of-advanced-directives.pdf?sfvrsn=550049b1_6 (February 6, 2021)
  • 47 American Academy of Nursing Policy: Reconsideration of do not resuscitate orders in the surgical/procedural setting. (website) https://www.nursingoutlook.org/article/S0029-6554(15)00131-1/pdf (November 14, 2020).
  • 48 Burns J.P., Truog R.D. The DNR order after 40 years. N Engl J Med. 2016;375(6):504–506.
  • 49 Kopecky K., Pelletier P., Miller P. Strategies for collaborative consideration of patients’ resuscitation preferences. AMA J Ethics. 2020;22(4):E325–E332.
  • 50 Hickey T.R., Cooper Z., Urman R.D., Hepner D.L., Bader A.M. An agenda for improving perioperative code status discussion. A Case Rep. 2016;6(12):411–415.
  • 51 Bauman M., Killebrew S., Ziminicki K., Balint K. Do not resuscitate in the perioperative environment: a multidisciplinary quality improvement project. AORN J. 2017;106(1):20–30.
  • 52 Urman R.D., Lilley E.J., Changala M., Lindvall C., Hepner D.L., Bader A.M. A pilot study to evaluate compliance with guidelines for preprocedural reconsideration for code status limitations. J Palliative Med. 2018;21(8):1152–1156.
  • 53 Tanious M., Lindvall C., Cooper Z., Tukan N., Peters S., Streid J., Fields K., Bader A. Prevalence, management and outcomes related to perioperative medical orders for life sustaining treatment (MOLST) in an adult surgical population. Ann Surg. 2020;doi:10.1097/SLA.0000000000004675.
  • 54 Nabozny M.J., Kruser J.M., Steffens N.M., Pecanac K.E., Brasel K.J., Chittenden E.H., Cooper Z., McKneally M.F., Schwarze M.L. Patient-reported limitations to surgical buy-in: a qualitative study of patients facing high-risk surgery. Ann Surg. 2017;265(1):97–102.
  • 55 Loeb A.E., Jia S.Y., Humbyrd C.J. Case commentary: what should an anesthesiologist and surgeon do when they disagree about terms of perioperative DNR suspension. AMA J Ethics. 2020;22(4):E283–E290.
  • 56 Anderson L.W., Holmber M.J., Berg K.M., Donnino M.W., Granfeldt A. In-hospital cardiac arrest: a review. JAMA. 2019;321(12):1200–1210.
  • 57 Fins J.J. Resuscitating patient rights during the pandemic: COVID-19 and the risk of resurgent paternalism. Cambridge Quarterly Healthcare Ethics. 2020;1-7.
  • 58 Maves R.C., Downer J., Dichter J.R., Hick J.L., Devereux A., Gerling J.A., Kissoon N., Hupert N., Niven A.S., King M.A., Robinson L.L., Haufling D., Hodge J.G., Marshall M.F., Fisch K., Evans L.E., Tonelli M.R., Wax R.S., Seda G., Parrish J.S., Truog R.D., Spring C.L., Christian M.D. Triage of scarce critical care resources in COVID-19: an implementation guide for regional allocation. Chest. 2020;158(1):212–225.
  • 59 Gupta R., Morain S.R. Equitable allocation of future COVID-19 vaccines. J Med Ethics. 2020;doi:10.1136/medethics-2020-106850.
  • 60 Clark C.M., Kenski D. Promoting civility in the OR: an ethical imperative. AORN J. 2017;105(1):60–66.
  • 61 Fast I., Villafranca A., Henrichs B., Magid K., Christodoulou C., Jacobson E. Disruptive behavior in the operating room is under-reported: an international study. Can J Anaesth. 2020;67(2):177–185.
  • 62 DeRenzo E.G. Privacy and confidentiality. In: Fletcher J.S., Spencer E.M., Lombardo P.A., eds. Fletcher’s introduction to clinical ethics. ed 3 Hagerstown, MD: University Publishing Group; 2005.
  • 63 Hanssen I., Jacobson I.L.S., Skramm S.H. Non-technical skills in operating room nursing: ethical aspects. Nurs Ethics. 2020;27(5):1364–1372.
  • 64 Blomberg A.C., Bisholt B., Lindwall L. Value conflicts in perioperative practice. Nurs Ethics. 2019;26(7-8):2213–2224.
  • 65 Blomberg A.C., Bisholt B., Lindwell L. Responsibility for patient care in perioperative practice. Nurs Open. 2018;27(5):414–421.
  • 66 Wendler M.C., Smith K., Ellenburg W., Gill R., Anderson L., Spiegel-Thayer K. “To see with my own eyes”: experiences of family visits during phase 1 recovery. J Perianesth Nurs. 2017;32(1):45–57.
  • 67 Pagnard E., Sarver W. Family visitation in the PACU: an evidence-based practice project. J Perianesth Nurs. 2019;34(3):600–605.
  • 68 Lee E., Li N., Yates A. Magnet journey: A quality improvement project—implementation of family visitation in the PACU. J Perianesth Nurs. 2015;30(1):39–49.
  • 69 American Society of PeriAnesthesia Nurses. Practice recommendation 9: Family presence in the perianesthesia setting. In: ASPAN, eds. 2021-2022 Perianesthesia Nursing Standards, Practice Recommendations and Interpretive Statements. ASPAN; 2020:80–84.
  • 70 Voncina G., Newcomb P. Effects of enhanced family visitation in postanesthesia services. J Perianesth Nurs. 2016;31(5):415–421.
  • 71 Odom-Forren J. Responsible social networking. J Perianesth Nurs. 2012;27(1):61–63.
  • 72 Brous E., Olsen D.P., Douglas P. Lessons learned from litigation: legal and ethical consequences of social media. AJN. 2017;117(9):50–54.
  • 73 Harper M.G., Maloney P. Nursing professional development: scope and standards of practice. ed 3 Chicago, IL: Association for Nursing Professional Development; 2016.
  • 74 Abbasinia M., Ahmadi F., Kazemnejad A. Patient advocacy in nursing: a concept analysis. Nurs Ethics. 2019;27(1):141–151.
  • 75 Beitz J.M. Addressing the perioperative nursing shortage through education: a perioperative imperative. AORN J. 2019;10(4):403–414.
  • 76 Denier Y., Dhaene L., Gastmans C. You can give them wings to fly: a qualitative study on values-based leadership in health care. BMC Med Ethics. 2019;20(1):35–52.
  • 77 Wakeman D., Langham M.R. Creating safer operating room: groups, team dynamics and crew resource management principles. Semin Pediatr Surg. 2018;27(2):107–113.
  • 78 American Society of PeriAnesthesia Nurses. Principles of safe perianesthesia practice. In: ASPAN, eds. 2021-2022 Perianesthesia Nursing Standards, Practice Recommendations and Interpretive Statements. ASPAN; 2020:14–15.
  • 79 Halladay M.L., Thompson J.A., Vacchiano C.A. Enhancing the quality of the anesthesia to postanesthesia care unit patient transfer through use of an electronic medical record-based handoff tool. J Perianesth Nurs. 2019;34(3):622–632.
  • 80 Lopez-Parra M., Porcar-Andreu L., Arizu-Puigvert M., Pujol-Caballe G. Cohort study on the implementation of a surgical checklist from the operating room to the postanesthesia care unit. J Perianesth Nurs. 2020;35(2):155–159.
  • 81 Halterman R.S., Gaber M., Janjua M.S.T., Hogan G.T., Cartwright S.M. Use of a checklist for the postanesthesia care unit patient handoff. J Perianesth Nurs. 2019;34(4):834–841.
  • 82 ERAS Guidelines for Perioperative Care (website) https://erassociety.org/guidelines/list-of-guidelines/. Published 2020. Accessed January 28, 2021.
  • 83 Scott M. Why patients should care about ERAS, Richmond Times Dispatch Op-Ed 2/12/2019.
  • 84 Watson D.J., Poisson C. Department-wide implementation of an enhanced recovery pathway: barriers and facilitators. In: Ljungqvist O., Francis N.K., Urman R.D., Cham R.D., eds. Enhanced recovery after surgery: a complete guide to optimizing outcomes. Springer International Publishing; 2020.
  • 85 Rutledge D.N., Retrosi T., Ostrowski G. Barriers to medication error reporting among hospital nurses. J Clin Nurs. 2018;27(9-10):1941–1949.
  • 86 Cole D.A., Bersick E., Skarbek A., Cummins K., Dugan K., Grantoza R. The courage to speak out: a study describing nurses’ attitudes to report unsafe practices in patient care. J Nurs Manage. 2019;27(6):1176–1181.
  • 87 Levine K.J., Carmody M., Silk K.J. The influence of organizational culture, climate, and commitment on speaking up about medical errors. J Nurs Manag. 2020;28(1):130–138.
  • 88 Spencer E.M. A case method for consideration of moral problems. In: In Fletcher J.S., Spencer E.M., Lombardo P.A., eds. Fletcher’s introduction to clinical ethics. ed 3 Hagerstown, MD: University Publishing Group; 2005.
  • 89 Lo B. Resolving ethical dilemmas: a guide for clinicians. ed 6 Philadelphia, PA: Wolters Kluwer; 2020.

Only gold members can continue reading. Log In or Register to continue

Stay updated, free articles. Join our Telegram channel

May 20, 2023 | Posted by in NURSING | Comments Off on Ethics in Perianesthesia Nursing

Full access? Get Clinical Tree

Get Clinical Tree app for offline access