Moral theory and the ethical practice of nursing





Learning Objectives


Upon the completion of this chapter and with further self-directed learning you are expected to be able to:




  • Explain moral justification.



  • Discuss critically the importance of moral justification to moral decision-making and action.



  • Outline the relationship between moral justification, moral theory and moral conduct.



  • Define ethical principlism.



  • Discuss critically how the moral principles of autonomy, non-maleficence, beneficence and justice might be used to guide decision-making in nursing and health care contexts.



  • Discuss critically a moral rights theory of ethics and its application in nursing practice.



  • Discuss critically the theory of virtue ethics.



  • Examine the relationship between virtue theory, an ethic of care and nursing ethics.



  • Distinguish between deontological and teleological ethics.



  • Differentiate between a moral right and a moral duty.



  • Discuss critically the limitations and weaknesses of contemporary moral theory.





Introduction


When encountering an ethical problem during the course of their work, nurses are confronted by at least three basic questions:




  • 1

    What should I do in this situation?


  • 2

    What is the ‘right’ thing to do?


  • 3

    How can I be sure (and be reassured) that my decisions and actions in the situation at hand are ‘morally right’, all things considered? In short, how can I be sure that I am behaving ethically and doing the ‘right thing’?



In seeking answers to these questions, it would be natural for a nurse to incline towards and draw on his / her own personal values, beliefs, professional knowledge and life experience. Whether this would be sufficient to provide the moral warranties or ‘moral authorisations’ being sought is another matter, however. Deciding the ‘morally right’ thing to do in a situation and taking moral action accordingly is rarely a straightforward process. Among other things it requires a broadly informed, systematic, insightful and deeply experienced approach to thinking about the issues at stake and how best to resolve them. This, in turn, requires ‘mastery’ and ‘not just surface competence’ of relevant ethical concepts and principles as well as ‘the skill to navigate them when they tangle together in concrete situations’ ( Little 2001 : 35).


Most people have strong beliefs and opinions about the world. No matter how sincerely held, however, beliefs and opinions can sometimes be mistaken. For example, there was a period in history when people sincerely believed that the world was square and that if they sailed to the edge of it they would drop off. Although a sincere belief, the view that the world was square was obviously mistaken, as explorers and scientists later proved. People now hold very different beliefs about the shape and geology of the world and it is conceivable that these too may be challenged and changed in the future.


Most people also have strong beliefs and opinions about what constitutes ‘right’ (good) and ‘wrong’ (bad) conduct. Moral beliefs, like other kinds of beliefs, can be mistaken, however, as centuries of moral inquiry have shown. Indeed, the philosophical literature is full of examples demonstrating convincingly (and giving good reasons for accepting) that some moral decisions and actions are clearly better than others (e.g. acts of compassion are better than acts of cruelty), and that some moral beliefs and theories seem manifestly ‘wrong’ and ought to be rejected (e.g. women lack moral capacity, black people have no moral worth, gay and transgendered people are moral deviants, Nazis had a moral obligation to rid the German nation of its ‘Jewish disease’, and so on).


It is because moral beliefs and opinions can be misguided, misinformed and mistaken – and because people can make mistakes in their moral judgments – that those at the forefront of moral decision-making must provide strong ‘warranties’ (good reasons) for their decisions and actions. It is not acceptable for a person to claim that his / her point of view is more worthy and more moral than another’s (is ‘right’) just because it is his / her point of view. For instance, I cannot claim that my point of view counts more or is more ‘right’ than your point of view just because it is my point of view. Much more is required – namely, there must be a sound justification for holding the point of view that is put forward. I must give good reasons why reasonable thinking and ‘right minded’ people should accept the point of view I am advancing. The question that arises here is: What constitutes a ‘sound justification’?


In the discussion to follow, attention will be given to clarifying the nature and importance of justification to moral decision-making and the role of ethical theory (in particular, ethical principlism, moral rights theory and virtue ethics) in providing justification and warranties (moral reasons) for nurses’ moral decisions and actions in the workplace.




Moral justification


Moral conflicts and disagreements occur frequently in health care contexts. This is not surprising given the ‘value ladenness’ of the health care practices that occur in health care domains. And given the complexity of the values that operate in health care domains, sometimes the choices we make will be ‘problematic’ insofar as they may express moral values, beliefs and evaluations that are not shared by others or which others do not agree with.


When experiencing situations involving moral disagreement and conflict, it is tempting to rely on our own ordinary moral experience and personal preferences to sustain the point of view we are advocating. As mentioned previously, however, sometimes our own ‘ordinary moral experience’ and personal preferences may not be reliable or worthy action guides because, as Kopelman (1995 : 117) warns us, these can result from ‘prejudice, self-interest or ignorance’. In light of this, we need to look elsewhere to strengthen the warranties of (in short, to justify) our moral choices and actions. Moral theory (which has as its focus showing why something is moral in addition to showing that it is moral) is commonly regarded as the definitive source from which such warranties (justifications) can be reliably sought.


Justifying a moral decision or action involves providing the strongest moral reasons behind them. However, as Beauchamp and Childress (2013) explain, merely providing a list of reasons will not suffice to justify a decision. This is because, ‘Not all reasons are good reasons, and not all good reasons are sufficient for justification’ ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 : 390). For example, a majority public opinion supporting the legalisation of euthanasia may constitute a good reason for decriminalising euthanasia yet stop short of providing a sufficient reason for doing so. Other ‘good and sufficient’ reasons will need also to be put forward demonstrating why public opinion is not relevant or adequate to justify the legalisation of euthanasia, such as: majority opinion tells us only that a certain class of people hold a point of view, not whether that point of view is morally right (euthanasia could still be morally wrong despite a majority view to the contrary); public opinion is notoriously fickle and hence unreliable as a moral action guide – what is deemed ‘right’ by the majority today could equally be deemed ‘wrong’ tomorrow (violating the standards of consistency and coherency otherwise expected in the case of sound moral decision-making). Decision-makers thus need not only to provide ‘strong reasons’ for their decisions and actions, but also to distinguish:



a reason’s relevance to a moral judgment from its sufficiency to support that judgment, [and also] to distinguish an attempted justification from a successful justification. ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 : 390 [emphasis original])


Here, relevance can be measured by the extent to which the reason (belief) has direct bearing on and makes a material difference to the evaluation made as part of the process aimed at making moral judgments and choices / decisions. Adequacy can, in turn, be measured by the extent to which it fulfils a need or requirement (in this instance to provide sufficient grounds for belief or action) without being outstanding or abundant. An attempt is simply to ‘make an effort’; to succeed is ‘to accomplish’.


Jaggar and Tobin (2013 : 385) similarly argue that although our ‘best available moral reasoning provides the most authoritative guide we have for morally appropriate action’ it may still be insufficient particularly in contexts where people disagree on the methods, models and practices of justification. This problem may be compounded in situations where the disputants do not trust each other’s knowledge claims ( Tobin 2011 ). To help overcome this problem, they propose four conditions of adequacy that must be met:




  • Plausibility – produce conclusions that have genuine moral force / weight (i.e. that are not arbitrary)



  • Usability – disputants are able to participate in the reasoning practices being used to justify an act



  • Non-abuse – the reasoning practices do not take wrongful advantage of power and vulnerability (i.e. misrepresent or distort evidence, use intimidation, fallacious logic (‘dirty tricks’ logic), ridicule or disregard disputants in order to discredit their views)



  • Practical feasibility – reasoning must be intelligible and able to be followed apropos prescribing a course of action (adapted from Jaggar & Tobin 2013 : 386–9).



Despite its importance to prescribing and proscribing human conduct, the notion of moral justification is not without difficulties. One reason for this is that there exist a number of different accounts of what constitutes a plausible model of moral justification, and even of how a given or ‘agreed’ model of justification might be interpreted and applied ( Bauman 1993 ; Beauchamp & Childress 2013 ; Dancy 1993 ; Jaggar & Tobin 2013 ; Kopelman 1995 ; Nielsen 1989 ; Tobin 2011 ; Tobin & Jaggar 2013 ). Some even suggest, controversially, that there can be no adequate model of justification since there is always room to question the grounds that are put forward as ‘good reasons’ supporting a particular act or judgment (see, for example, Hughes 1995 ; Johnston 1989 ). The adequacy of conventional approaches to moral justification has particularly been called into question in contexts involving population diversity and inequality. Tobin and Jaggar (2013 : 413), for example, contend that philosophers have tended to seriously underestimate the challenges that cultural diversity and socio-economic inequality can (and does) pose to achieving trustworthy moral justifications in real-world settings. One reason for this, they contend, is because there has been an ‘invidious idealization’ of privileged models of justification which, either wittingly or unwittingly, can be used as tools for domination and repression ( Jaggar & Tobin 2013 : 402, 404).


The problem of moral justification has long been recognised as a crucial one in moral philosophy. As Kai Nielsen reflects (1989 : 53):



In ordinary non-philosophical moments, we sometimes wonder how (if at all) a deeply felt moral conviction can be justified. And, in our philosophical moments, we sometimes wonder if any moral judgments ever are in principle justified. Surely, we can find all sorts of reasons for taking one course of action rather than another. We find reasons readily enough for the appraisal we make of types of action and attitudes. We frequently make judgments about the moral code of our own culture as well as those of other cultures. But how do we decide if the reasons we offer for these appraisals are good reasons? And, what is the ground for our decision that some reasons are good reasons and others are not? When (if at all) can we say that these grounds are sufficient for our moral decisions? [emphasis original]


There are three possible answers to these questions raised by Nielsen – namely, that we can appeal to either: (1) moral rules, principles and theories; (2) lived experience and case examples of individual personal judgments and the moral insights gained by reflecting on these; or (3) a synthesis of both these (theoretical and experiential) approaches (see also Chappell 2009 ). This approach, unlike the other approaches, involves a strong synergy between theory and practice, with each informing the other and neither being immune to revision. This issue will be explored more fully in Chapter 5 , Moral problems and moral decision-making in nursing and health care contexts.




Theoretical perspectives informing ethical practice


Western moral philosophy has given rise to many different and sometimes competing theoretical perspectives or viewpoints on the nature and justification of moral conduct. Having some knowledge and understanding of these different perspectives is crucial not just to enhancing our understanding of the complex nature of moral problems and the controversies and perplexities to which they so often give rise, but also to enhancing our abilities to provide satisfactory solutions to the moral problems we encounter in our everyday lives. Unfortunately it is beyond the scope of this book to give an in-depth account of the many ethical theories that have been and remain influential in Western moral philosophical thought. There are, however, three theoretical frameworks that warrant attention here – namely, those that involve respectively (and sometimes interdependently) an appeal to:



  • 1

    ethical principles ( ethical principlism )


  • 2

    moral rights ( moral rights theory )


  • 3

    moral virtues ( virtue ethics ).

These three approaches, each informed by the traditions of western moral philosophy, have emerged as having the most currency and credibility in contemporary health care contexts. Reasons for this include:


  • they have largely emerged from and been refined by practice



  • they are able to be readily applied to and in practice



  • they are amendable so can be revised and refined in order to be more responsive to the lived realities of everyday practice.



Ethical principlism


One of the most popular theoretical perspectives used today when considering ethical issues in health care is the perspective called ‘ ethical principlism ’. Ethical principlism is the view that ethical decision-making and problem-solving are best undertaken by appealing to sound moral principles. The principles most commonly used are those of: autonomy, non-maleficence, beneficence and justice. These principles are generally accepted as providing sound moral reasons for taking moral action.


Although not free of difficulties, ethical principlism has become widely accepted as a reliable and practical framework for identifying and resolving moral problems in health care contexts. Given the dominance of ethical principlism in contemporary discussions on ethical issues in health care (largely because of the influential work on the topic by Beauchamp & Childress (2013) ), it is important that nurses have some knowledge and understanding of this approach.


What are ethical principles?


Ethical principles are general standards of conduct that make up an ethical system. To say that a principle is ‘ethical’ or ‘moral’ is merely to assert that it is a behaviour guide which ‘entails particular imperatives’ ( Harrison 1954 : 115). In this instance the imperatives involve specification (in the form of prescriptions and proscriptions) that some type of action or conduct is prohibited, required, or permitted in certain circumstances ( Solomon 1978 : 408). By this view, an action or decision is generally considered morally right or good when it accords with a given relevant moral principle, and morally wrong or bad when it does not. To illustrate how this works, consider the action of making a measurement using a ruler. If the line you have drawn measures the desired length of, say, 12 cm – as measured against your ruler – you would judge the length as ‘correct’. If, however, the line you have drawn is only 10 cm long – not the desired 12 cm – you would judge the length to be ‘incorrect’. By analogy, principles also function like rulers, insofar as they provide a standard against which something (in this case, actions) can be measured. For example, if an action fails to ‘measure up’ to the ultimate standards set by a given principle, we would judge the action to be ‘incorrect’ or, more specifically, morally wrong. If, however, an action fully measures up to the ultimate standards set by a given principle, we would judge the action to be ‘correct’ or morally right. The next question is: What are these moral principles against which actions can be measured?


As stated earlier, moral principles commonly used in discussions on ethical issues in nursing and health care include the principles of autonomy, non-maleficence, beneficence and justice. It is to briefly examining the content, prescriptive force and application of these principles that this discussion now turns.


Autonomy


The term ‘ autonomy ’ comes from the Greek autos (meaning ‘self’) and nomos (meaning ‘rule’, ‘governance’ or ‘law’). When autonomy is used as a concept in moral discourse, what is commonly being referred to is a person’s ability to make or to exercise self-determining choice – literally, to be ‘self-governing’. Included here is the additional notion of ‘respect for persons’ – that is, of treating or respecting persons as ends in themselves, as dignified and autonomous choosers, and not as the mere means (objects or tools) to the ends of others ( Benn 1971 ; Kant 1972 ). The principle of autonomy, however, is a little different, and is eloquently formulated by Beauchamp and Walters (1982 : 27) as follows:



Insofar as an autonomous agent’s actions do not infringe on the autonomous actions of others , that person should be free to perform whatever action he or she wishes (presumably even if it involves considerable risk to himself or herself and even if others consider the action to be foolish). [emphasis added]


What this basically means is that people should be free to choose and are entitled to act on their preferences provided their decisions and actions do not stand to violate, or impinge on, the significant moral interests of others.


Both the concept and the principle of autonomy have important implications for nursing practice. For example, if autonomy is to be taken seriously by nurses, nursing practice must truly respect patients as dignified human beings capable of deciding what is to count as being in their own best interests – even if what they decide is considered by others (including nurses) to be ‘foolish’. In short, nurses must allow patients to participate in decision-making concerning their care. Given this, it soon becomes clear that the whole practice of ‘negotiated patient goals’ and ‘negotiated patient care’ as advocated by contemporary nursing philosophy has its roots in the moral principle of autonomy and the derived duty to respect persons as autonomous moral choosers. It is not derived merely from a concept of ‘acceptable professional nursing practice’.


In application, the principle of autonomy would judge as being morally objectionable and wrong any act which unjustly prevents autonomous persons from deciding what is to count as being in their own best interests. The kinds of act which might come in for criticism here include, for example:




  • treating patients without their consent



  • treating patients without giving them all the relevant information necessary for making an informed and intelligent choice



  • withholding information from patients when they have expressed a considered choice to receive it



  • imposing information upon patients when they have expressed a considered choice not to receive it



  • forcing nurses to act against their reasoned moral judgments or conscience.



It should be noted, however, that while the moral principle of autonomy is helpful in guiding ethically just practices in health care contexts it is not entirely unproblematic. Indeed, its uncritical and culturally inappropriate application in some contexts may, in fact, inadvertently cause rather than prevent significant moral harms to patients, for reasons which are considered in Chapter 4 .


Non-maleficence


The term ‘ non-maleficence ’ comes from the Latin-derived maleficent – from maleficus (meaning ‘wicked’, ‘prone to evil’), from malum (meaning ‘evil’), and male (meaning ‘ill’). As a moral principle, non-maleficence (literally ‘refuse evil’), prescribes ‘above all, do no harm’ which entails a stringent obligation not to injure or harm others. This principle is sometimes equated with the moral principle of ‘beneficence’ (considered below under a separate subheading) which prescribes ‘above all, do good’. Trying to conflate these two obviously distinct principles under one principle is, however, misleading. As Beauchamp and Childress (2013 : 151) explain, not only are these two principles distinct (for instance, our obligation not to kill someone does seem qualitatively and quantitatively different from our obligation to rescue someone from a life-threatening situation), but it is important to distinguish between them so as not to obscure other critical moral distinctions which might be made in ordinary moral discourse. One instance in which ‘other important distinctions might need to be made’ is in the case of where both principles might apply to a given situation, but where the strength of the respective moral imperatives of each may nevertheless differ significantly and thus might prescribe different courses of action.


‘Stringentness’ thus stands as an important distinction that might be obscured if the principles of non-maleficence and beneficence were conflated into one single principle. Beauchamp and Childress (2013 : 151) contend that generally ‘obligations of non-maleficence are usually more stringent than obligations of beneficence’, and, in some cases, may even override beneficence particularly in instances where beneficent acts (e.g. to help others and to provide benefits), paradoxically, are not morally defensible (e.g. depriving one’s family of food for a week and risking eviction by failing to pay the rent because of donating the household’s weekly budget to charity). However, Beauchamp and Childress (2013 : 151) further contend that, while our obligations not to harm others might be more stringent in some situations than our obligations to help them, the reverse can also be true (e.g. the justified ‘harm’ of radical yet lifesaving and ‘beneficial’ surgery).


Applied in nursing contexts, the principle of non-maleficence would provide justification for condemning any act which unjustly injures a person or causes them to suffer an otherwise avoidable harm.


Before continuing, some commentary is warranted on the notion of ‘harm’ and how it might be interpreted (given that it is open to a variety of interpretations). For the purposes of this discussion, harm may be taken to involve the invasion, violation, thwarting or ‘setting back’ of a person’s significant welfare interests to the detriment of that person’s wellbeing ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 : 153–4; Feinberg 1984 : 34). Interests, in this instance, are taken to mean ‘a miscellaneous collection, consist[ing] of all those things in which one has a stake’ together with the ‘harmonious advancement’ of those interests ( Feinberg 1984 : 34). Interests are morally significant since they are fundamentally linked to human wellbeing; specifically, they stand as a fundamental requisite (although, granted, not the whole) of human wellbeing ( Feinberg 1984 : 37). Wellbeing, in turn, can include interests in:



continuance for a foreseeable interval of one’s life, and the interests in one’s own physical health and vigour, the integrity and normal functioning of one’s body, the absence of absorbing pain and suffering or grotesque disfigurement, minimal intellectual acuity, emotional stability, the absence of groundless anxieties and resentments, the capacity to engage normally in social intercourse and to enjoy and maintain friendships, at least minimal income and financial security, a tolerable social and physical environment, and a certain amount of freedom from interference and coercion. ( Feinberg 1984 : 37)


The test for whether a person’s interests and wellbeing have been violated, ‘set back’, thwarted or invaded rests on ‘whether that interest is in a worse condition than it would otherwise have been in had the invasion not occurred at all’ ( Feinberg 1984 : 34). For instance, if a person (e.g. a patient) is left psychogenically distressed (e.g. in emotional pain, anxious, depressed and even suicidal) or in a state of needless physical pain and / or disability as a result of his / her experiences (e.g. as a patient in a given health care setting) our reflective commonsense tells us that this person’s interests have been violated and the person him / herself ‘harmed’. As the American philosopher Joel Feinberg (1984 : 37) further explains, the violation of a person’s welfare interests renders that person ‘very seriously harmed indeed’ since ‘their ultimate aspirations are defeated too’.


Beneficence


The term ‘beneficence’ comes from the Latin beneficus , from bene (meaning ‘well’ or ‘good’) and facere (meaning ‘to do’). The principle of beneficence prescribes ‘above all, do good’; in practice, it entails a positive obligation to literally act for the benefit of others, viz contribute to the welfare and wellbeing of others ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 ). Acts of beneficence can include such virtuous actions as: care, compassion, empathy, sympathy, altruism, kindness, mercy, love, friendship and charity. It is recognised, however, that bestowing benefits on others is not always without cost to the benefactor. Thus there are some limits to the principle; that is, it is not ‘free standing’ and its application can be appropriately constrained by other moral (e.g. utilitarian) considerations. To put this another way, we are not obliged to act beneficently towards others when doing so could result in our own significant moral interests being seriously harmed or compromised in some way.


Although the notion of ‘obligatory beneficence’ remains a controversial one in moral philosophy (for instance, it is generally accepted that we are not morally required to benefit persons on all occasions, even if we are in a position to do so), there are nevertheless a number of conditions under which a person can indeed be said to have an obligation of beneficence and that this obligation might, sometimes, be overriding. An example of such conditions, devised by Beauchamp and Childress (2013 : 207), is as follows:



a person X has a prima facie obligation of beneficence, in the form of a duty to rescue, toward person Y if and only if each of the following conditions is satisfied (assuming X is aware of the relevant facts):

  • 1.

    Y is at risk of significant loss of or damage to life, health or some other basic interest.


  • 2.

    X’s action is needed (singly or in concert with others) to prevent this loss or damage.


  • 3.

    X’s action (singly or in concert with others) will probably prevent this loss or damage.


  • 4.

    X’s action would not present significant risks, costs, or burdens to X.


  • 5.

    The benefit that Y can be expected to gain outweighs any harms, costs, or burdens that X is likely to incur.



The principle and its prescribed obligation of beneficence stands to have an interesting and useful application in nursing practice. Consider the following hypothetical case. Mrs Jones, a Jehovah’s Witness, is admitted to an intensive care unit in the final stages of life, suffering from advanced hepatitis B and severe liver failure. She has a slow internal haemorrhage and is only semiconscious. Before her alteration in consciousness she gives her doctors a written statement specifically requesting that she not be given a blood transfusion under any circumstances. Upon her arrival in the unit, however, the attending doctor prescribes a unit of blood and requests that it be given immediately. Mrs Jones’ husband and children are all present and, upon overhearing the doctor’s request, become very upset. Mr Jones approaches the doctor and asks that his wife not be given the blood transfusion. He reminds the doctor that Mrs Jones has made explicit her wish not to have a blood transfusion under any circumstances. Nurse Smith, the registered nurse caring for Mrs Jones, hears the discussion and is faced with deciding whether or not to intervene on her patient’s behalf. In making her decision, Nurse Smith might appeal to the principle of beneficence in the following manner:



  • 1

    Mrs Jones, a Jehovah’s Witness in the final stages of life, is at risk of suffering a significant loss (a violation of her spiritual values and beliefs) if she is given the medically prescribed blood transfusion.


  • 2

    Action by Nurse Smith, the attending nurse, is needed to prevent Mrs Jones from experiencing the loss in question.


  • 3

    Nurse Smith’s action of refusing to administer the prescribed transfusion would probably prevent Mrs Jones’ loss.


  • 4

    Nurse Smith’s action will not present a significant risk to her (i.e. she will not lose her job).


  • 5

    The benefits gained by Mrs Jones outweigh any harms Nurse Smith is likely to suffer (given that Nurse Smith autonomously chooses to uphold Mrs Jones’ interests, and does not stand to suffer any morally significant consequences of her actions).



Weighing up the benefits and burdens, Nurse Smith decides to refuse to give the transfusion which has been prescribed. The doctor, however, insists that it be given. In response to this, the nurse points out that the transfusion would probably be of no clinical benefit to Mrs Jones, as she was clearly in the end stages of her disease – to put it bluntly, ‘she was dying’. Nurse Smith then suggests to the doctor that perhaps he would prefer to administer the transfusion himself. The doctor rejects this suggestion, and the transfusion is not given. Mrs Jones dies a short while later without having to experience a needless violation of her expressed wishes, values and beliefs.


In summary, by this principle, any act which fails to address an imbalance of harms over benefits where this can be done without sacrificing a benefactor’s own significant moral interests warrants judgment as being morally unacceptable.


Justice


The principle of justice (its nature and content), unlike the principles above, is not so amenable to precise definition or quantification. Questions concerning what justice is and what its origins are have occupied the minds of philosophers for nearly 3000 years, and to this day remain the subject of philosophical debate ( MacIntyre 1988 ; Nussbaum 2006 ; Powers & Faden 2006 ; Sen 2009 ; Solomon & Murphy 1990 ). Significantly, the end result of this protracted philosophical debate has not been the development of a singular and refined universal theory of justice, but rather that of a range of rival theories of justice – both traditional and recent ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 ; MacIntyre 1988 ). Different conceptions of justice (from the Latin justus meaning ‘righteous’) have included: justice as revenge (retributive justice – e.g. ‘an eye for an eye’), justice as mercy (Christian ethics), justice as harmony in the soul and harmony in the state (Pythagorean ethics, 600 bc –1 ad ), justice as equity (impartiality and fairness), justice as avoiding parochialism and reducing (global) injustice , justice as equality (‘equals must be treated equally, and unequals unequally’), justice as an equal distribution of benefits and burdens (distributive justice and redistributive justice), justice as what is deserved (‘each according to one’s merit or worth’), and justice as love ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 ; MacIntyre 1988 , 2007; Nozick 2007 ; Nussbaum 2006 ; Outka 1972 ; Powers & Faden 2006 ; Rawls 1971 ; Sen 2009 ; Singer 1991 ; Solomon & Murphy 1990 ; Waithe 1987 ). Over the past two decades, justice has also been conceptualised as reconciliation and reparation (restorative justice), a key purpose of which is to ‘restore broken relationships’ ( Tutu 1999 ; see also Johnstone G 2002 ; Sullivan & Tifft 2006 ). Arguably one of the most novel conceptions of justice is that of justice as a basic human need that, like other basic human needs (notably those famously depicted in Maslow’s hierarchy of human needs), is critical to producing the necessary conditions of life ( Taylor 2003 , 2006 ).


Given these different conceptions of justice, the problem arises of what, if any, conception of justice nurses should adopt? While it is beyond the scope of this book to answer this question in depth, there is nevertheless room to advocate at least three senses of justice which nurses might find helpful: (1) justice as fairness and impartiality (equity justice), (2) justice as the equal distribution of benefits and burdens (distributive and redistributive justice), and (3) justice as reconciliation and reparation (restorative justice). It is these three senses of justice which will now be considered.


Justice as fairness and impartiality (equity)


Justice as fairness finds interpretation in terms of ‘what is owed or due’ ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 : 250). By this view, it can be said that one acts justly towards a person when that person has been given what is due or owed; an injustice, in turn, would involve withholding from that person what is otherwise due or owed.


If a person deserved something, justice is done when that person receives that particular something. Here, the ‘something’ may be either positive (a reward) or negative (a punishment). This view relies very heavily on an ‘intuitive’ sense of justice. For example, we may ‘feel’ it is unjust to punish or censure someone for a harm they did not cause, or not to punish someone for a harm they did deliberately cause. Likewise we may feel that it is unjust to reward someone for an accomplishment to which they contributed nothing, and yet not reward someone who contributed a great deal.


We do not need to look far in nursing practice to find sobering examples of where the principle of justice as fairness has been violated. Consider the notable historical cases where nurses have been subjected to severe legal and professional censure, held solely responsible and have even lost their jobs because of making an honest mistake ( Johnstone 1994a ; Johnstone & Kanitsaki 2006b ).


Other examples involve cases where nurses have gained promotion or have secured employment on the basis of their claiming credit for the work of either their peers or their subordinates. At the other end of the continuum, some nurses have been denied promotion or employment because their superior has ignored, or refused for whatever reasons to recognise significant professional achievements the nurse applicant has in fact made.


How, then, might we make choices on this view of justice? One possible approach which has received widespread attention is that discussed by the contemporary American philosopher John Rawls. He argues, for example, that if parties are to exercise truly just or fair choices, they must choose from a hypothetically ‘neutral’ position, or from a position of what he describes as being ‘behind the veil of ignorance’ ( Rawls 1971 : 12). From such a position he argues:



no-one knows his [sic] place in society, his [sic] class position or social status, nor does anyone know his [sic] fortune in the distribution of natural assets and abilities, his [sic] intelligence, strength, and the like … [T]his ensures that no-one is advantaged or disadvantaged in the choice of principles by the outcome of natural chance or the contingency of social circumstances. Since all are similarly situated and no-one is able to design principles to favour his [sic] particular condition, the principles of justice are the result of a fair agreement or bargain. ( Rawls 1971 : 12)


While Rawls’ view is problematic (it is open to serious question whether, in fact, all choosers are or could ever be ‘similarly situated’, as he assumes), it has nevertheless been extremely influential. A key reason for its influence relates to broader philosophical demands that are inherent in Western bioethics and which emphasise, among other things, that moral choice and judgment should be exercised from a position of impartiality and objectivity . However, whether in fact human beings are ever capable of exercising truly impartial and ‘objective’ choices – indeed, of choosing from behind that veil of ignorance – remains a matter of some controversy. Some critics also argue that Rawls’ theory is too narrow, pointing out that it has failed to take a more responsive approach to social cooperation and the needs of people who are disabled, ‘not equal’, disadvantaged, and who belong to other non-human species (see Nussbaum 2006 ; Sen 2009 ). One reason for this is that it pays too much attention to patterns of distribution, rather than to the ‘procedural issues of participation, deliberations and decision-making’ ( Young 2007 : 600). Moreover, Rawls’ theory fails to take into account that what is important is not just the distribution of benefits and burdens per se, but how various distributions came about ( Nozick 2007 ).


Despite its weaknesses, Rawls’ justice theory provides a useful catalyst for thinking about the notion of fairness and how it might be used in real-life situations. It also alerts us to some of the potential difficulties of trying to determine and apply an uncontentious view of justice.


Justice as an equal distribution of benefits and burdens


A second (and related) sense in which justice can be used is that pertaining to ‘distributive justice’ – that is, an equal distribution of benefits and harms. Benefits in this instance may be taken to mean ‘primary goods’ – things we can assume all reasonable people would want such as health, liberty, civil and political rights, income security, etc.; harms, in turn, may be taken to mean the untoward consequences of an unequal distribution of society’s ‘primary goods’ and their associated benefits.


By this view of justice, all people are required to bear an equal share of their society’s benefits and burdens. Such a view admits that all persons must have equal claims to liberty and opportunity, but in a way that is compatible with the claims of others. As well as this, there must be equal access (and opportunity to gain access) to positions of authority and power, and there must be an equal distribution of wealth and income (a point often missed in conservative constructions of justice as equity – such as outlined above). The only morally acceptable exception to this would be if an unequal distribution would work to everyone’s advantage, or where an unequal distribution of benefits would be necessary so as to prevent unequal disadvantage. Simply put, inequalities in distributing benefits and primary goods is ‘just’ as long as this results in the least well-off (i.e. those who are already disadvantaged unfairly) achieving a decent minimum level of wellbeing (i.e. being advantaged by the benefits which have been conferred unequally).


As with the fairness sense of justice discussed earlier, we do not need to look far to find sobering examples in nursing where the principle of distributive justice has been violated. In many cases, nurses have had to (and continue to) bear unequal and intolerable burdens on account of certain inequities in the distribution of scarce health care resources. For example, historically nurses have had to endure poor and unsafe working conditions with a maximum of responsibility and a minimum of financial or personal reward ( Johnstone M-J 1994a , 2002 ).


In calculating the balance or distribution of harms and benefits, notions of comparative and non-comparative justice are used. In the second edition of their foundational work, Beauchamp and Childress (1983: 185) explain that justice is ‘comparative’ when ‘what one person deserves can be determined only by balancing the competing claims of others against his or her claims’. For example, whether a nurse qualifies for a job or a promotion will depend largely on the competing claims of the other applicants. If the other applicants are more qualified and more experienced, it seems reasonable to hold that they are more ‘deserving’ of the position being offered. Justice is ‘non-comparative’, on the other hand, when ‘desert is judged by standards independent of the claims of others’ ( Beauchamp & Childress 1983 : 185). For example, a nurse who is guilty of breaching acceptable professional standards of conduct deserves to be censured, or even deregistered, if the breach of conduct warrants such an action; a nurse who is innocent of professional misconduct, however, does not deserve to be censured or deregistered.


Justice as reconciliation and reparation


A third (and less well known) sense in which justice can be used is in a reconciliation and reparative sense, otherwise referred to as ‘restorative justice’. In contradistinction to retributive justice (the primary aim of which is to assign blame and punish offenders), restorative justice has as its primary aim:



healing rather than hurting, moral learning, community participation and community caring, respectful dialogue, forgiveness, responsibility, apology and making amends. ( Braithwaite 1999 : 6)


Historically, small societies have often used means other than retribution to ‘resolve conflict and restore harmony’ ( Maxwell & Morris 2006 : 72). Thus, instead of using punishment to redress a wrong, processes for promoting healing and restoration have been emphasised ( Johnstone G 2002 ; Maxwell & Morris 2006 ; Sullivan & Tifft 2005 , 2006 ). This approach has, however, also worked in large nations. A poignant example of this can be found in the extraordinary case of South Africa’s Truth and Reconciliation Commission (TRC), which commenced in May 1996 following the collapse of the apartheid regime in that country. Based on the Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation Act, 1995 (available for viewing at: www.doj.gov.za/trc/ ), the TRC was conducted in the spirit of ubuntu , an African jurisprudence principle which emphasises ‘the healing of breaches, the redressing of imbalances, the restoration of broken relationships’ ( Tutu 1999 : 51). Although severely criticised by some for its ‘religious components’ (notably the promulgation of the assumptions that ‘truth is a precursor to forgiveness’ and ‘forgiveness is necessary for healing’) and the demonstrable negative impact it had on the mental health of some individuals and families ( Swartz & Drennan 2000 ), the TRC is nonetheless credited with being an instrument of national healing. It has also been credited with providing a ‘third way’ for redressing the past and to enable the country to move forward and not descend into mayhem and civil war, as has happened so often in other countries where people have suffered years of oppression and brutality ( Tutu 1999 ).


Over the past two decades, restorative values have also been translated and applied in practice as a form of ‘therapeutic jurisprudence’ in the cultural contexts of New Zealand, Canada, the United States (US) and Australia. Although primarily advanced as an Indigenous Justice Initiative aimed at assisting in the rehabilitation of young offenders from Indigenous communities and ‘restoring’ them to their communities (see Braithwaite 1999 ; Johnstone G 2002 ; Maxwell & Morris 2006 ; Sullivan & Tifft 2005 , 2006 ), restorative justice has also been applied in broader contexts. Some notable examples include its use to improve compliance with regulatory standards in health care contexts (see Freckelton & Flynn 2004 ; Makkai & Braithwaite 1994 ), and to rehabilitate and restore community and population health ( Ashworth 2002 ; Freudenberg 2001 ). As the negative health consequences of individual as well as institutional injustices become more apparent (see Herndon 1992 ; Taylor 2003 , 2006 ), the need of a ‘third way’ to resolve conflict and restore harmony – to find out the truth, heal breaches, redress imbalances, restore broken relationships (after Tutu 1999 : 51) and rehabilitate both victims and perpetrators injured by an offence without resorting to a system of retributive justice ( Johnstone G 2002 ; Johnstone & Van Ness 2007 ) – will become more pressing, and the possible remedies offered by restorative justice compelling as both a ‘moral measure’ and a moral course of action.


Moral rules


Moral principles are not the only entities that make up an ethical system or ethical framework for guiding conduct. Moral rules also have a place in guiding and ‘warranting’ ethical conduct. Like moral principles, moral rules function by specifying that some type of action or conduct is either prohibited, required or permitted ( Solomon 1978 : 408–9). What distinguishes a moral rule from a moral principle in certain contexts is its structure and nature. Moral principles, for instance, tend to be regarded as providing the content of morality, and the bases or the ‘parent’ forms from which general moral truths (insofar as these can be determined) are derived. In application, moral principles incline more towards a general focus. Consider, for example, the broad moral principle of ‘autonomy’. In general, the principle prescribes that persons should be respected as autonomous choosers, capable of judging what is in their own best interests. As such, people who have the capacity to make autonomous decisions should be free to act as they wish provided their actions do not violate the moral interests of others.


Moral rules, on the other hand, stand as being merely derivative of moral principles and theories and, in application, are much more particular in their focus. Although it is difficult to draw a firm distinction between moral rules and moral principles, it is generally recognised that moral rules have different force, sanctioning power, conditions of existence, scope of application and level of concreteness from moral principles ( Solomon 1978 ). An example of a moral rule would be the demand, say, to ‘always tell the truth’ or ‘never tell a lie’. Thus, if a patient asks an attending health care professional a question concerning a diagnosis and proposed treatment, the health care professional could be said to be obliged to give the information the patient has requested. The apparent ‘obligation’ here finds its force not just from the moral rule ‘always tell the truth’, but from the moral principle of autonomy which prescribes that people with the capacity to make self-interested decisions should be respected as autonomous choosers, and be given the information required to make an informed and intelligent choice.


Another example can be found in a set of rules that prescribe such things as ‘do not kill others’, ‘do not cause pain and suffering to others’, ‘do not affect detrimentally the physical and mental health of others’, and so forth. The apparent obligations here find their force not just from the rules stated, but also from the moral principle non-maleficence, which prescribes ‘do no harm’.


In order for a particular moral rule (or set of moral rules) to be justified, it must be fully derived from and reducible to established parent principles of morality.


In summary, moral rules derive from moral principles, and as such have only prima-facie force (i.e. they can be overridden by stronger moral claims). Given their prima-facie nature, moral rules cannot override the moral principles from which they have been derived. To accept that they could, would be to suggest, somewhat paradoxically, that derived rules could meaningfully conflict with parent principles – which is absurd. The relationship between particular moral judgments, moral rules, moral principles and moral theories is shown in Fig. 3.1 .




FIGURE 3.1


Moral justification and direction of appeal

(Adapted from: Beauchamp T & Childress J (1994) Principles of biomedical ethics , 4th edn. Oxford University Press, New York: 15)


The question of moral rules is an important one for nurses, particularly as it relates to the broader issue of professional codes of conduct, an issue that will become clearer in the following chapters.


Problems with ethical principles


In considering ethical principlism it is important to be aware of a number of difficulties that can arise when appealing to the ethical principles described. For example, problems commonly associated with ethical principlism include:




  • deciding correctly which principles apply in a given situation (e.g. ‘Is it the principle of autonomy or beneficence that applies in this case, or both?’)



  • interpreting correctly the imperatives of the principles chosen to guide ethical decision-making in a given situation (e.g. ‘What does the principle of autonomy require of me? Is it the case that the principle of autonomy ought always to be upheld?’)



  • deciding correctly the relative weights of given principles (e.g. ‘Which principle has overriding consideration in this case – the principle of autonomy or the principle of non-maleficence?’)



  • balancing the demands of different principles in situations where their respective though equally weighted demands might conflict (e.g. ‘How can I uphold the principle of autonomy without, at the same time, violating the principle of justice, which has an equal bearing in this case?’)



  • deciding whether ethical principles apply at all (e.g. ‘This is a matter to be resolved by kindness and care – by being virtuous – not by appealing to ethical principles per se.’)



  • resolving disagreement with others regarding either of the above (e.g. ‘I feel strongly that respecting the patient’s autonomy in this case means withholding the information about his diagnosis as he has requested, but others in the team do not agree and are going to tell him, insisting he must be told so that he can make informed choices about his future treatment.’).



The issue of moral uncertainty, moral dilemmas and moral disagreements in regard to the selection, interpretation and application of ethical principles will be explored further in the chapters to follow.


Moral rights theory


Of the moral theories that have been appealed to in the contemporary literature on ethics, a ‘rights’ view of ethics is probably the one that has the most currency among professional and lay communities alike. Certainly most people have a sense that they have ‘rights’, that their rights are ‘justified’ ( Martin 2017 ) and that their rights, whatever these may be, ‘ought to be respected’. Important questions to ask are: ‘What are moral rights?’, ‘Who has them?’ and ‘To what extent are others obliged to respect them?’


Moral rights theory has emerged as an extremely influential theoretical perspective across the globe. Evidence of this can be found in the vast array of contexts in which moral rights discourse has been used. For example, we see moral rights discourse in: position statements and bills of clients’ / patients’ rights; professional codes of ethics and conduct (e.g. the International Council of Nurses’ Code for nurses ( ICN 1973 , 2012a ) and supporting position statements); statutory authorities (e.g. the various Australian state and territory Human Rights and Equal Opportunity Commissions); government inquiries (e.g. the Report of the National Inquiry into the Human Rights of People with Mental Illness by Burdekin et al 1993 ); and in international covenants, conventions and treaties (e.g. the United Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights ( United Nations 1949 ), and the ratification of The International Bill of Human Rights ( United Nations 1978 )). There is also an abundance of literature on the subject. If nurses are to participate effectively in discourses on moral rights, it is essential that they have some understanding of the theoretical underpinnings of a moral (and human) rights perspective on ethics. It is to providing a brief examination of moral rights theory that this section will now turn.


Moral rights


Moral rights (to be distinguished here from human rights, legal rights, institutional rights, civil rights, etc.) generally entail claims about some special entitlement or interest which ought, for moral reasons, to be protected. The kinds of interests for which protection might be sought include, for example, life, freedom, happiness, privacy, self-determination, fair treatment and bodily integrity. The language used in asserting rights typically involves expressions such as: ‘I have a right to …’, ‘It’s your right to …’, ‘They have a right to …’, and so on. A rights claim is generally accepted as a sound moral reason for taking moral action.


There is no single thesis of moral rights. The following is a brief overview of some of the better-known classical and contemporary theories concerning the existence of moral rights and the conditions under which they can be validly claimed.


Moral rights based on natural law and divine command


Natural rights theory argues that certain entitlements are simply ‘built into’ the universe like the laws of gravity, and as such are neither the products of human invention nor the constructs of other moral theories ( Martin & Nickel 1980 ). A variation of this thesis is that natural rights have been divinely ordained for all human beings. From both these points of view, since the laws of nature and the ordinances of God apply equally to all human beings, it follows that all human beings – young and old; male, female, transgender and intergendered (e.g. hermaphrodites); homosexual, heterosexual and bisexual; abled and disabled; black, white and coloured – unconditionally have natural rights.


Objections to this account of moral rights derive from those raised against a theological account of morality generally. For example, if it were shown that God did not exist, or that natural law did not exist, this account of moral rights would immediately collapse because its very foundation would be pulled out from underneath it. Another objection rests on the problem that natural rights essentially defy scientific verification.


Moral rights based on common humanity


Another popular natural rights thesis is that all human beings have rights simply by virtue of being ‘human’ and ‘equal’. What is critical to this thesis is the notion that ‘being human’ is something over which we have no control; that is, we cannot choose to be either human or not human ( Martin & Nickel 1980 ). In this sense, then, we can be said to enjoy a ‘common humanity’. This view of rights is vulnerable to the objection that not all human rights are moral rights per se. The human right to education, which is dependent on the availability of educational resources, is an example of a human right which is not a moral right per se.


Another more serious problem is that, given the recent advancements made in the field of genetic engineering, ‘being human’ may indeed be something over which we have control in the near future. Human genes have already been cloned onto animals (e.g. pigs and fish); it is not far-fetched to imagine that scientists will succeed (if they have not already done so) in cloning animal genes onto humans. Persons with a genetic makeup comprising both human and non-human genes could be said to be not ‘fully human’, at least, not in a ‘speciesist’ sense. Were someone to be not ‘fully human’, their claim to moral rights on the basis of a common humanity would be cast in doubt. Conversely, if a non-human nonetheless has human genes and / or human characteristics (e.g. chimpanzees that are capable of performing abstractions), it too might hold claim to what are otherwise upheld as being exclusively ‘human rights’ (see also Dershowitz 2004 : 143).


Moral rights based on rationality


A Kantian thesis of natural rights (i.e. a thesis based on the philosophical views of the German philosopher Immanuel Kant circa 1724–1804) holds rationality as being the sole basis upon which a right’s claim can be made. In other words, only those people who are capable of rational, autonomous thought are entitled to claim moral rights. One disturbing consequence of this thesis is that any human being (or non-human being, for that matter) who is unable to reason is not regarded as having moral status. Such a view clearly excludes infants, brain-dead and intellectually disabled persons, and others with severe organic brain states corrosive of their ‘personhood’ from having a just claim to moral rights. It might be tempting to dismiss this view as being merely an intellectual one, of interest only to moral philosophers. There is ample evidence, however, that this view is influential and has currency in the ‘real world’ of human affairs. (The most notable examples here can be found in the use of ‘brain-dead’ persons, fetuses and live-born anencephalics as organ donors ( Bioethics Committee, Canadian Paediatric Society 2005 ; Fost 2004 ; Khan & Lea 2009 ; Meinke 1989 ; Siminoff 2004 ).)


Moral rights based on interests


The North American philosopher Joel Feinberg offers quite a different theory of moral rights. He argues that, in order for an entity to be able to claim rights meaningfully, that entity must have interests ( Feinberg 1979 ). To have interests, the entity must be capable of being either benefited or harmed. In order to be either benefited or harmed, one must have the capacity to experience pleasure and pain – that is, have sentience. In short, unless one has sentience one cannot have interests, and thus cannot be either benefited or harmed, and therefore cannot make claims.


Some have taken this view even further contending that ‘sentience is the bedrock of ethics’, not just of moral rights ( Balcombe 2016 : 13). This is because it is fundamentally wrong to ‘deliberately and maliciously cause another pain and suffering’ because pain and suffering are in themselves fundamentally bad ( Balcombe 2016 : 13). This theory of moral rights can be expressed diagrammatically as shown in Fig. 3.2 .




FIGURE 3.2


Feinberg’s theory of moral rights


It can be seen that by this view it would be nonsense to assert, for example, that a rock has rights. Why? Because a rock does not have sentience and therefore cannot, strictly speaking, be benefited or harmed, and thus cannot meaningfully be said to have interests, and hence rights. Those who value rocks (e.g. conservationists, geologists, rock collectors) might be benefited or harmed by what happens to a rock, but it is not meaningful, philosophically speaking, to assert that a rock per se has rights. In contrast, any entity which can be shown to have sentience (i.e. the capacity to experience pleasure or suffer pain) would, by this view, be entitled to be respected as having rights. Given this, it is clear that we can, for example, assert meaningfully that beings such as dolphins, puppies, kittens, horses, people who cannot think or reason or express their wishes because of an incapacitating brain injury or other debilitating brain disease, and babies have moral rights.


Like Bentham, the founding father of utilitarianism (to be discussed later in this chapter), Feinberg sees the capacity to suffer , not reason, as the ultimate basis upon which a person’s interest claims become the focus of moral action.


One shortcoming of this view is that individuals must be able to represent their own interests. Feinberg (1979 : 595) argues that, if individuals cannot represent their own interests, they have no more rights than ‘redwood trees and rosebushes’. Unhappily, the ‘human vegetable’, it seems, is no better off under an interests-based thesis of moral rights than it is under a thesis based on reason.


Feinberg does not, however, offer an adequate account of why entities must be able to ‘represent their own interests’. As contemporary theorists have recently shown, human beings (especially those who are vulnerable) do not necessarily ‘have to be capable of making claims, or have the capacity to function as a moral agent in order to have rights’ ( Dyck 2005 : 116). Feinberg also fails to account for why others (who are capable of making sound judgments about the moral interests of vulnerable persons and acting in a way to protect those interests) cannot speak for individuals, families and groups when they are unable or incapable of speaking on their own behalf. Moreover, there is considerable scope to suggest that an interests-based thesis of moral rights justifies and, in some contexts, even demands surrogate representation – particularly in the case of human beings who are vulnerable and unable (because of their age, impairment of cognitive function, physical confinement, political oppression, emotional distress, and so forth) to ‘speak for themselves’ and / or effectively represent their own best interests ( Hoffmaster 2006 ; Kottow 2003 , 2004 ; Purdy 2004 ).


Moral rights based on human experiences of grievous wrongs


Not all agree with the above theories of the origins of rights. Dershowitz, for example, a leading legal scholar from Harvard University, argues that human rights do not derive from God, nature, logic, or otherwise, but from ‘particular human experiences’ – notably of the ‘worst injustices’ and ‘most grievous wrongs’ and the ongoing quest by reasonable people to prevent their reoccurrence and to ‘righting the wrongs’ that have occurred ( Dershowitz 2004 : 81–2). With reference to some of the world’s most potent historical examples of ‘worst injustices’ and ‘most grievous wrongs’ (genocide and slavery being two standout examples), Dershowitz (p 90) contends:



Where the majority does justice to the minority, there is little need for rights. But where injustice prevails, rights become essential. Wrongs provoke rights, as our checkered history confirms.


Drawing on this observation, and advancing a thesis of ‘nurtural rights’ (to be distinguished from ‘natural rights’), he concludes that human rights thus have their origin in human wrongs , and that, in essence, a theory of rights is ipso facto also a theory of wrongs ( Dershowitz 2004 : 81).


An important question to arise here is: How are we to know what are ‘most grievous wrongs’? Dershowitz suggests, first, that ‘if wrongs were not wrongs’, then it is reasonable to ask why their perpetrators go to such lengths to hide or disguise them – pointing out that ‘even Hitler and his henchmen tried to hide their genocidal actions behind euphemisms and evasive rhetoric’ ( Dershowitz 2004 : 81). Second, there is likely to be more agreement than not among reasonable people as to what constitute ‘most grievous wrongs’. On this point Dershowitz (2004 : 83) argues:



Reasonable people will always disagree about the nature of the perfect good, but there will be less disagreement about the evils that experience has taught us to prevent.


Finally, and arguably most propitiously, is the burgeoning of rights themselves immediately after a most grievous wrong has been acknowledged, as numerous examples in history can readily demonstrate (the formulation and ratification of the United Nations Declaration of Human Rights being just one example) ( Dershowitz 2004 : 94–5). Importantly, rights can also ‘quickly contract’ in the aftermath of wrongs ‘believed to be caused by excessive rights’ claims ( Dershowitz 2004 : 95) – an issue that is explored further under the subheading ‘Rights and responsibilities’ in this chapter.


Dershowitz (2004 : 232) concludes that ‘righting wrongs’ is an ongoing process that will see rights in a constant state of flux as they adapt and counter each new injustice. Accordingly, those who believe in rights must ‘take their case to the people’ and must engage in the positive project of constantly proving that ‘rights work’, that ‘they are necessary to prevent wrongs, and that they are worth the price we sometimes pay for them’.


Different types of rights


When speaking of moral rights, it is important to distinguish three different types which can be claimed, notably: inalienable, absolute and prima-facie rights.


Inalienable rights


An inalienable right is one which cannot be transferred under any circumstances. For example, if we accept the right to life as being an inalienable right, we are committed to accepting that it cannot be transferred to someone else or for some other cause under any circumstances. According to this view, sacrificing one’s life in suicide, martyrdom, or in an act of supreme altruism (e.g. a mother sacrificing her life for her child) would be deemed as morally wrong. Of course, we may ask the question whether the right to life is an inalienable right.


Absolute rights


An absolute right, by contrast, is a right which cannot be overridden under any circumstances. For example, if we take the right to life as being absolute, we would be bound to respect it whatever the cost. By this view, any wilful taking of human life, whether through war, self-defence, abortion, capital punishment, or any other act, would be morally wrong. Here the question arises whether the right to life really is an absolute right.


Prima-facie rights


A prima-facie (from the Latin primus , meaning ‘first’, and facies , meaning ‘face’) right is a right which may be overridden by stronger moral claims. For example, a patient’s right to privacy may be overridden by the right to life in a cardiac arrest situation where the patient’s body is exposed during the resuscitation procedure. In such an emergency, it would be misguided for an ethicist to insist that the patient’s right to privacy should take priority in the situation at hand.


Some argue against the notion of prima-facie rights by saying that if a right can be overridden it does not exist. Against such a criticism, Martin and Nickel (1980 : 172–4) comment:



to describe a right as Prima Facie is to say something about its weight but not about its scope or conditions of possession … Overridence depends on whether the case of conflict is central to the values that the right serves to protect or whether it is a marginal case and thus can be expected in all cases without great loss to those values.


Making rights claims


Having a right usually entails that another has a corresponding duty to respect that right ( Martin 2017 ). As Feinberg (1978 : 1508) explains, when people assert their moral rights, they assert a kind of ‘moral power’ over us which we feel constrained to respect. Where claims have a special convincing force they have a coercive effect on our judgments, which in turn make us feel driven to both acknowledge and support the interest claims being made as being genuine rights claims.


Rights which entail a corresponding duty are typically referred to as ‘claims rights’. These rights can be either positive or negative, and can entail either a positive or a negative rights claim. Positive rights claims generally entail a correlative duty to act or to do, in contrast with negative rights claims, which generally entail a correlative duty to omit or to refrain ( Feinberg (1978 : 1509). For example, if a patient claims a right not to be harmed, this claim imposes a negative duty on an attending nurse to refrain from acts which may cause harm. On the other hand, if a patient claims a right to be benefited in some way, such as by having an intolerable pain state relieved, this imposes a duty on an attending nurse to perform the positive act of promptly administering an effective analgesic. If a person’s rights claims are not upheld, or are infringed or violated in some way, that person generally feels wronged or feels a serious injustice has been done. In a rights view of ethics, if someone claims a right this is generally regarded as providing a ‘moral reason’ (a warranty) for taking moral action.


Rights and responsibilities


Any discussion on moral rights would not be complete without also considering the responsibilities that rights holders have when choosing to claim or exercise their rights in given contexts. The need to take into account the moral responsibilities associated with rights claims has become especially pressing in recent years on account of the rise-and-rise of ‘unrestricted isolated individualism’ (also called ‘rampant individualism’) in English-speaking democracies of the developed world (e.g. the United States, the United Kingdom (UK), Canada, Australia, New Zealand, and so forth) (see Dyck 2005 ; Glendon 1991 ; Nussbaum 2006 ; Young 1990 ). Paradoxically, this rampant individualism – sometimes decried in terms of ‘people having all rights and no responsibilities’ – is threatening to weaken and even nullify the very system of rights that, up until now, has served the significant moral interests of individuals, groups and even whole communities whose wellbeing has been at serious risk and even substantially harmed because of oppression, exploitation, violence and other harmful human behaviours perpetrated by more powerful and dominant others.


In recent years there has been increasing recognition (and criticism) of the tendency in classical moral rights theory to fail to take into account the fundamental connection between rights and responsibilities and, in particular, the responsibility that rights’ holders have to exercise their rights in a just and responsible manner . This stance has given rise to a ‘new’ view of rights, notably, as a just expectation – that is, a state of being characterised by ties of mutually expected responsibilities to one another, as individuals and as members of groups and institutions ( Dyck 2005 : 117).


Referring to the classic works of the 19th century British philosopher John Stuart Mill, Dyck (2005 : 115) contends that, since rights are fundamentally rooted in justice, then rights must themselves be exercised ‘justly’. Quoting Mill (‘Justice implies something which is not only right to do, and wrong not to do, but which some persons can claim from us as his [sic] moral right’), Dyck (p. 115) explains that, since justice is itself a ‘moral responsibility’, in the context of rights claims this imposes an obligation on people:



(1) to honour rights that justifiably claim one or another of our various moral responsibilities, and (2) to claim from other individuals, groups, or institutions only those actions for which they can be held morally responsible.


Dyck goes on to caution that irresponsible rights claims stand to not only violate the principle of justice but also, in doing so, weaken the claims themselves. Irresponsible claims thus stand as ‘violations’ (i.e. of ‘just expectations’ that bona fide rights claims will be exercised responsibly) that, in turn, threaten to tear (and, as racial violence and civil war can readily attest, has torn) the moral fabric of communities apart. Dyck further cautions that unless individuals, groups and social institutions claiming rights ‘are willing and able to act responsibly’ – by which he means ‘act to maintain the moral bonds of community’ – then those rights ‘are not and cannot be actualised’ ( Dyck 2005 : 114). In other words, the failure to exercise rights claims justly and responsibly could nullify the rights claims altogether, something that could have serious consequences at both a practical and a theoretical level. In contrast, exercising given rights claims justly and responsibly actually strengthens the rights claims being made. Moreover, by recognising the responsibilities that come with rights, claimants help to form and maintain what Dyck (p 132) calls the ‘inhibitions against causing evil’, notably, ‘destroying individuals and human relations’ and the human wellbeing that is otherwise so dependent on these relations being maintained in a manner that is just and nurturing.


Problems with rights claims


In discussing rights it is important to keep in mind at least six central problems that can arise when dealing with rights claims. First, rights and interests can seriously compete and conflict with one another. For example, a patient’s right to life could seriously compete or conflict with another patient’s right to life in a situation involving scarce medical resources; or a nurse’s conscientious refusal to assist with an abortion procedure could conflict with a patient’s right to have an abortion and to receive care following the procedure. In such instances there may be no easy solution to the conflict of interests at hand.


Second, it may be difficult to establish the extent to which a person’s rights claim entails a correlative duty. For example, if someone claims a right to life, who or what has the corresponding duty to respond to that claim? Does it fall to the health professional, or to family, friends, the hospital, the state or another entity? There may be no satisfactory answer to this question.


Third, there may be disagreement about which entities have rights. For example, some might argue that brain-dead people, anencephalic babies, the intellectually impaired and babies do not have moral rights, while others might argue that they do. Again there may be no satisfactory resolution to this type of disagreement.


Fourth, it may be very difficult to try and satisfy the rights claims of all people equally. For instance, if there is a genuine lack of resources, it may be impossible to satisfy all rights claims. Once again, we are left, unhappily, with an unresolved moral problem.


Fifth, it may be very difficult to determine what counts as a responsible or an irresponsible rights claim and the conditions under which an irresponsible rights claimant might forfeit his or her entitlements (have their rights claims nullified).


Sixth, and more seriously, is the controversial claim that moral rights theory is not a comprehensive moral theory at all as, among other things, it is unable to explain, account for or justify the significance and motives of people’s actions ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 : 374). At best, it is argued, rights theory amounts to little more than a ‘statement of minimal and enforceable rules protective of individual interests that communities and individuals must observe’ ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 : 374).


On account of these and other difficulties, some have sought to avoid a moral rights perspective altogether, or at least to replace the language of rights. (For example, when referring to people’s moral entitlements, instead of using ‘rights’ language some writers use such terms as ‘interests’, ‘welfare’, ‘wellbeing’, and so on.) Others, however, defend the use of rights language despite the theoretical weaknesses of a moral rights perspective. Beauchamp and Childress (2013) , for example, point out that, for many scholars, political activists and others, rights theory is probably the ‘most important type of theory for expressing the moral point of view’ ( p. 367 ). They go on to explain:



No part of the moral vocabulary has done more in recent years to protect the legitimate interests of citizens in political states than the language of rights. Predictably, injustice and inhumane treatment occur most frequently in states that fail to recognise human rights in their rhetoric, actions and documents. As much as any part of moral discourse, human rights language crosses international boundaries and enters into international law and statements by international agencies and associations. ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 : 374–5)


Others have taken a similar stance adding that rights discourse has a ‘high reputation’ and, for all its weaknesses, continues to enjoy ‘pervasive popularity’ in the world at large ( Campbell 2006 : 1, 5). Reasons for the success of rights discourse have been identified by Campbell (2006 : 1, 5) as involving the strong association it has with the language of:






  • imperatives (‘To have a right is to have something that overrides other considerations in both moral and legal discourse’)



  • individualism (‘A society based on rights is believed to manifest and affirm the dignity of each and every human life as something that is deserving of the highest respect’)



  • remedies (‘Rights are not associated with simply aspiring to do what is good or desirable but demand restraint, redress and rectification of wrong done in violation of rights’)



  • decisiveness (‘By establishing what it is right and just to do, rights in particular circumstances and excluding other considerations as being of lesser significance, rights promise clear answers to moral problems’)



  • security (‘Having rights enables us not only to enjoy certain benefits but to have knowledge that they are ours “by right” and cannot therefore be taken away at the whim of others’)



  • universality (‘The generality of rights offers protection to individuals against arbitrary treatment, a feature which is most evident when universal rights are ascribed to all persons irrespective of the race, religion, class or gender’).



The issue of moral rights is an important one for nurses – particularly as the issue relates to patients’ rights, to the People’s Health Movement (PHM), and also to the relationship that exists between health and human rights – all of which have been receiving increasing attention in recent years. As these are substantial issues in their own right, they are considered separately in Chapter 6, Chapter 7, Chapter 8, Chapter 9, Chapter 13 of this book.


Virtue ethics


In recent times there has been a resurgence of virtue theory in ethics and a re-examination of the importance of ‘characterological excellence’ as an ingredient of authentic moral conduct ( Athanassoulis 2013 ; Hursthouse 1999 , 2007 ; van Hooft 2006 ; van Hooft et al 2013 ). Virtue ethics holds a particular relevance for nursing since virtuous conduct is intricately linked to therapeutic healing behaviours and the promotion of human wellbeing.


Virtue ethics (also known as character ethics) has an impressive history dating back to the ancient philosophical and theological texts of both Western and non-Western cultures ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 ; Hursthouse 1999 , 2007 ; Kruschwitz & Roberts 1987 ; Pellegrino 1995 ; van Hooft et al 2013 ). As Pellegrino (1995: 254) writes, ‘Virtue is the most ancient, durable, and ubiquitous concept in the history of ethical theory.’


Despite its durability, virtue theory has nonetheless been in various stages of decline over the past several centuries – particularly within the field of Western moral philosophy. This decline can be traced to the rise of scientism. By the late 17th and 18th centuries, for instance, the ‘Enlightenment project of finding a rational justification for morality’ saw moralists look away from the law of God ‘to actual, observable human nature for a justification of traditional moral norms’ (MacIntyre 2007: 39; Kruschwitz & Roberts 1987 : 12–13). Although virtue ethics has retained its currency in some fields – for example the medical profession up until as late as the 1970s ( Pellegrino 1995 : 264), and the nursing profession up until the present time ( Armstrong 2006 , 2007 ; Begley 2006 ; McKie & Swinton 2000 ) – its importance to and in moral philosophy has long been lost, having been neglected by philosophers preoccupied with turning ethics into a science.


Significantly, since the 1980s, there has been a revival in virtue-based theories of ethics ( Athanassoulis 2013 ; Hursthouse 1999 , 2007 ; Pellegrino 1995 ; Pence 1984 ; van Hooft 2006 ; van Hooft et al 2013 ). This revival (which has included both religious and non-religious approaches to virtue theory) has been driven by an increasing dissatisfaction and frustration among some philosophers with the otherwise narrow, abstract, impersonal and at times oversimplified approach of traditional obligation-based theories of ethics, and the need to find an alternative approach that is more reflective of and responsive to the complexities of the moral life. Of particular concern has been the questionable neglect within mainstream moral philosophy of considerations relating to the moral character of moral agents (persons who engage in moral actions). One aspect of this concern is expressed eloquently by Pence (1991 : 256), who, commenting on what he sees as ‘a common defect in non-virtue theories’, points out:



On the theories of duty or principle, it is theoretically possible that a person could, robot-like, obey every moral rule and lead the perfectly moral life. In this scenario, one would be like a perfectly programmed computer (perhaps such people do exist, and are products of perfect moral educations).


The idea that persons could function as ‘moral robots’ is both disturbing and unsatisfactory to virtue theorists, and, it might be added, to others who feel at least an intuitive unease about the prospect of morality being merely a matter of following a set of rules. We do seem to think, as Clouser (1995 : 231) reminds us, that morality ‘also encourages us to act in ways that go beyond what is required’ – beyond a robot-like obedience to rules.


There does seem to be something ‘missing’ in the traditional picture of ‘the moral life’. For virtue theorists, this ‘something’ is character. As Pence (1991 : 256) writes:



we need to know much more about the outer shell of behaviour to make such [moral] judgments, i.e. we need to know what kind of person is involved, how the person thinks of other people, how he or she thinks of his or her own character, how the person feels about past actions, and also how the person feels about actions not done.


Furthermore, there is a sense in which virtue theory is inevitable. As Pellegrino (1995 : 254) points out:



One cannot completely separate the character of a moral agent from his or her acts, the nature of those acts, the circumstances under which they are performed, or their consequences. Virtue theories focus on the agent; on his or her intentions, dispositions and motives; and on the kind of person the moral agent becomes, wishes to become, or ought to become as a result of his or her habitual disposition to act in certain ways.


Virtue theory raises some important questions, namely: (1) What is virtue?, (2) What constitutes a virtuous person? and (3) Given virtue theory, does virtue ethics offer a plausible and viable alternative to traditional obligation-based theories of ethics and the decision procedures they supply?


The notion of virtue


The term ‘virtue’ (from the Latin virtus meaning ‘manliness’, courage from vir meaning ‘man’) denotes the quality or practice of moral excellence. As an ingredient of moral theory, it can be defined as:



a trait or character that disposes its possessor habitually to excellence of intent and performance with respect to the telos specific to a human activity. Virtue gives to reason the power to discern and to will the motivation asymptomatically to accomplish a moral end with perfection. ( Pellegrino 1995 : 268)


There are many examples of ‘the virtues’ (see, for example, the 52 virtues listed by the Virtues Project at www.virtuesproject.com/ , which are presented as core ingredients that people may use to ‘create a culture of character’). Some examples of the better-known moral virtues include: altruism, caring, compassion, cooperation, courage, diligence, empathy, excellence, fairness (justice), forgiveness, friendship, generosity, kindness, love, loyalty, personal integrity, reliability, respectfulness, sympathy, trustworthiness and wisdom ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 ; Hursthouse 1999 , 2007 ; Kruschwitz & Roberts 1987 ; Pellegrino 1995 ; van Hooft 2006 ; van Hooft et al 2013 ).


The virtuous person


The notions of ‘virtue’ and ‘virtuous persons’ are both universal constructs. As Pellegrino (1995 : 255) points out:



Every culture has a notion of the virtuous person – i.e., a paradigm person, real or idealised, who sets standards of noble conduct for a culture and whose character traits exemplify the kind of person others in that culture ought to be or to emulate.


Such paradigm persons include: Buddha, Confucius, Jesus Christ, the Prophet Mohammed and, in more recent history, the Catholic nun Mother Teresa ( Vardey 1995 ), hailed for her charitable works in India. Buddha, for instance, is renowned for exemplifying such perfections of character as ‘forbearance, self-restraint, contentment, compassion, generosity, mildness, courage, meditation, and wisdom’ ( Hursthouse 2007 : 45). Confucianism, in turn, is renowned for its emphasis on ‘character traits that typify the good or noble person’, notably: humanity, benevolence, compassion, wisdom, righteousness, courage, trustworthiness, filial piety and propriety ( Hursthouse 2007 : 45). Islam, which takes a religious rather than a philosophical perspective on virtuous actions, places strong emphasis on doing ‘good deeds’ and upholding the key virtues taught in the Qur’an , notably of ‘justice, benevolence, piety, honesty, integrity, gratitude and chastity’ ( Halstead 2007 : 284).


The question remains: what is a virtuous person? In a purely virtue-based theory of ethics, morally exemplary (virtuous) persons (including moral heroes and moral saints) are generally distinguished from other persons who ‘do their duty’ in a somewhat impersonal, impartial, universalistic rule-bound sense ( Blum 1988 ). In a purely virtue-based ethic, a virtuous person is taken to be ‘the good person, the person upon whom one can rely habitually to be good and to do the good under all circumstances’ ( Pellegrino 1995 : 254). A virtuous person may also be described as someone who is ‘truly excellent’ in action and feeling – who, as Hursthouse asserts (2007 : 50), ‘ “gets things right” in both action and feeling’.


Blum (1988) takes the notion of virtuous persons even further to include what he calls ‘moral heroes’ and ‘moral saints’. A moral hero, by his view, is someone:




  • who brings about a great good (or prevents a great evil)



  • who acts to a great extent from morally worthy motives



  • whose moral-worthy motives are substantially embedded in his or her own personal psychology



  • who carries out his or her moral project in the face of risk or danger



  • who is relatively ‘faultless’ or has an absence of unworthy desires, dispositions, sentiments, and attitudes (adapted from Blum 1988: 199, 203).



A moral saint, in contrast, is not altogether different from a moral hero, except for one feature. According to Blum (1988 : 204), moral saints share three features in common with moral heroes:



they are animated by morally-worthy motives, their morally-excellent qualities exist at a deep level of their personality or character, and they meet the standard of relative absence of unworthy desires.


The salient feature which distinguishes a moral saint from a moral hero, however, is that the moral saint exhibits ‘a higher standard of faultlessness’ viz the absence of unworthy desires ( Blum 1988 : 204).


Virtue theory, an ethic of care and nursing ethics


A virtue theory of ethics holds a particular pertinence for nursing ethics in terms of providing a theoretical foundation and justificatory framework for nurses’ moral decision-making and actions when providing nursing care. One reason for this can be found in the fundamental link between ‘the virtues’ and ‘the right attitudes’ or ‘characterological traits’ (e.g. of care, compassion, empathy, presence) that are generally recognised as being both essential to and constitutive of a healing health-professional–client relationship – the nurse–patient relationship included.


Conversely, the professional ethics of nurses and in particular nursing’s ethic of care hold a promising prospect for virtue ethics – in that it provides a domain within which ‘the virtues’ can be shown to have both moral and practical clout. As Pellegrino (1995: 266) writes:



Unlike general ethics, professional ethics offers the possibility of some agreement on a telos – that is, an end and a good. In a healing relationship between a health care professional and a patient, most would agree that the primary end must be the good of the patient. The healing relationship, itself, provides a phenomenological grounding for professional ethics that applies to all healers by virtue of the kind of activity that healing entails. In general ethics, on the other hand, at least at present, the analogous possibility for agreement on something so fundamental as the telos, end, or good of human life is so remote as to be practically unattainable.


Pellegrino (1995 : 268–70) goes on to articulate seven virtues which he believes will define ‘the “good” physician, nurse or other health professional’ and which can be supplemented by other virtues:



  • 1

    ‘fidelity to trust and promise’ (encompassing a recognition of the importance of trust to healing)


  • 2

    ‘benevolence’ (noting that people seek to be helped not harmed)


  • 3

    ‘effacement of self-interest’ (to help protect patients against being exploited)


  • 4

    ‘compassion and caring’ (so that patients can be assisted in their healing in the fullest sense)


  • 5

    ‘intellectual honesty’ (to ensure competent practice)


  • 6

    ‘justice’ (‘removing the blindfold and adjusting what is owed to the specific needs of the patient, even if those needs do not fit the definition of what is strictly owed’) and


  • 7

    ‘prudence’ (encompassing the qualities of practical wisdom and the ability to deal effectively with complexity).



Pellegrino’s views can be readily applied to and indeed overlap with the tenets of nursing ethics. The agreed end or telos of the profession and practice of ‘good’ nursing is the promotion of health, healing and wellbeing, together with the alleviation of suffering, in individuals, groups and communities for whom nurses care. This end is a moral end, and one that carries with it a strong moral action guiding force for nurses insofar as it requires nurses to engage in the behaviours necessary to promote health, healing and wellbeing in people, and, when manifest, to alleviate their suffering. In light of these ends, and the nature of the means necessary to achieve them (i.e. ‘good’ nursing care), nursing thus stands fundamentally as a benevolent (virtuous) activity or, more precisely, a ‘moral practice’ that aims to discover (through assessment), make explicit and accomplish (through cooperation and negotiation) whatever is ‘good’ for (read as ‘conducive to the health, healing and wellbeing of’) the individuals, groups and communities for whose care nurses share responsibility ( Gastmans et al 1998 : 58).


In speaking of ‘good’ nursing care, it is important to clarify that something much more than merely ‘competent’ nursing care is being referred to. Rather, it is competent care integrated with a ‘virtuous attitude’ of caring. As Gastmans and colleagues explain (1998 : 45, 53):



It is only by integrating a virtuous attitude of caring with the competent performance of care activities ( caring behaviour ) that good care can be achieved … Morally virtuous attitudes are an integral part of nursing practice, since this practice takes place within a human relationship where the nurse and the patient are the main actors … This is in essence what is meant by caring behaviour: the integration of virtue and expert activity . [emphasis added]


‘Virtuous caring’ is integral to ‘good’ (moral) nursing practice (and, by implication, nursing ethics) in at least two important ways. First, virtuous caring or ‘right attitudes’ (which include the behavioural orientations of compassion, empathy, concern, genuineness, warmth, trust, kindness, gentleness, nurturance, enablement, respect, mutuality, ‘giving presence’ [being there], attentive responsiveness, mindfulness, providing comfort, providing a sense of safety and security, and others) have all been thoroughly implicated as effective nursing healing behaviours in the alleviation of human suffering (hence the notions in nursing of caring as healing and nursing as informed caring for the wellbeing of others) ( Armstrong 2006 , 2007 ; Geary & Hawkins 1991 ; Leftwich 1993 ; McKie & Swinton 2000 ; Swanson 1993 ). Such behavioural orientations have been demonstrated as making a significant and positive difference not only to a patient’s existential sense of – and actual – ‘wellbeing’, but also to the effectiveness of drugs, to wound healing, and even to survival itself (it is well known, for example, that premature newborns will ‘fail to thrive’ in the absence of attentive, ‘high-touch’ and informed nursing care and may even die; similarly, it is known that adults who are deprived of meaningful care will fail to heal and may even die prematurely from life-threatening diseases) ( Ching 1993 ; Dossey 1993 ; Gastmans et al 1998 ; Gaut & Leininger 1991 ; Kanitsaki 2000 ; Moore & Komras 1993 ).


Second, ‘virtuous caring’ plays an important theoretical role in providing an account of moral motivation in nursing to act in beneficent ways. For instance, whereas in obligation-based theories the motivation to act morally is thought to be derived from a rationally appraised commitment to ‘do one’s duty’, in the case of virtuous caring the motivation to be moral is derived from ‘v-rules’ (described in ‘ Problems with virtue ethics ’) informed by moral sentiment (for instance, caring about a thing in some way ( Rachels 1988 : 20)), and specifically a nurse’s affective involvement in (i.e. caring about) the patient’s wellbeing. The explanation of Gastmans and colleagues (1998 : 54) is worth quoting at length; they write:



In addition to the collection and availability of relevant information [to plan and implement patient care], the caring nurse needs to be affectively involved in the patient’s wellbeing. The caring nurse needs to be emotionally touched by what happens to the patient, both in a positive and a negative sense. The cognitive and affective dimensions of the virtue of care are not rightly understood as merely two separate components – a cognition and a feeling state – added together, rather they inform one another. The (altruistic) virtue of care is more than a passive feeling state that has a person in a state of woe as their object. The (altruistic) virtue of care involves an active, motivational aspect as well, relating to the promotion of beneficent acts aimed at helping the other person. In other words, the caring nurse must be motivated to respond to the appeal of the patient. Common to the altruistic virtue of care is a desire for, or regard for, the good of the other (for his or her own sake). This desire prompts (intended) beneficent action when the nurse is in a position to engage in it.


The agreed ethical standards of nursing require nurses to promote the genuine welfare and wellbeing of people in need of help through nursing care, and to do so in a manner that is safe, competent, therapeutically effective, culturally relevant and just. These standards also recognise that in the ultimate analysis nurses ‘can never escape the reality that they literally hold human wellbeing in their hands’ ( Taylor 1998 : 74), and accordingly must act responsively and responsibly to protect it. These requirements are demonstrably consistent with a virtue theory account of ethics. Thus, as Armstrong (2006 : 117) concludes, virtue ethics provides a distinct and credible theoretical basis for nursing ethics on account of its four central tenets:



  • 1.

    It provides a detailed account of moral character.


  • 2.

    It provides a rich account of moral goodness.


  • 3.

    It provides a plausible account of moral education.


  • 4.

    It provides a natural and convincing account of moral motivation.



Virtue ethics and an ethic of care in nursing – some further thoughts


Consistent with a virtue theory account of ethics is a nursing-specific articulation of an ‘ethic of care’ – long regarded by many nurse theorists as the moral foundation, essence, ideal and imperative of nursing ( Benner & Wrubel 1989 ; Bowden 1994 ; Carper 1979 ; Cooper 1991 ; Fry 1989a ; Gaut 1992 ; Leininger 1990a ; Roach 1987 ; Watson 1985 ). Despite this, there has been mounting criticism over the past few decades about the place of ‘care’ in nursing ethics and also about the nursing profession’s claim to be the exclusive guardians of care ( Barker et al 1995 ). These criticisms have ranged from describing an ethic of care as being ‘hopelessly vague’ and as ‘obscuring more than it promotes’ ( Allmark 1995 : 20) to rejecting that care is a virtue at all ( Curzer 1993 ). Still others denigrate care as an untenable form of ‘subjugation’ of women on account of its apparent ‘sexist service orientation’ that could see women (nurses) carrying a disproportionate ‘burden of care’ in a society (or a system) that is, for the most part, careless ( Puka 1989 : 21). A brief response to some of these criticisms is warranted here.


First, as just demonstrated, a reflective articulation of an ethic of care in relation to the moral ends of nursing helps to clarify the precise behaviours expected of a ‘good’ nurse. It not only prescribes ‘do good’, but also describes what those ‘goods’ are (the promotion of health, healing and wellbeing, and the alleviation of suffering), and how to achieve them (through an integration of expert and virtuous caring comprising a range of ‘healing-promoting behaviours’). Second, given the mutually beneficial nature of ‘virtuous caring’ (it has demonstrable positive outcomes for both the receiver and the giver of authentic virtuous care), there is room to suggest that ‘caring’ that is unjustly burdensome is not only not ‘virtuous caring’ but also not ethical. Arguments against ‘virtuous caring’ are thus not correctly aligned at the right target; they are, as it were, ‘attacking a straw man’. Third, the criticisms are not convincing. For instance, in the case of the criticism that an ethic of care could be unduly burdensome on women (nurses), it is not immediately clear why it would be any more burdensome than, say, an obligation-based theory of ethics. As the example of the Biblical story of Abraham demonstrates (Abraham came close to sacrificing his only son to fulfil his duty of obedience to God), ‘doing one’s duty’ can, in some circumstances, be an extremely burdensome thing to do and further may not be able to be done without sacrificing something of moral importance. Further, to suggest that nurses might in some way become enslaved or ‘subjugated’ by an ethic of care seems to imply erroneously that (and, it must be added, to perpetuate the patriarchal myth that) nurses qua nurses lack the discretion and moral competence necessary to decide for themselves what moral standards they will adopt and uphold; in short it seems to suggest, incorrectly in my view, that nurses will just ‘follow slavishly’ an ethic of care. Finally, these criticisms seem to overlook that an ethic of care is, paradoxically, protective of its practitioners in that it rejects symbiotic (over)emotional involvement with ‘the other’, emphasising instead moral virtue (characterological excellence) as its foundation ( Gastmans et al 1998 : 54–7).


If there remain lingering doubts about the fidelity and force of an ethic of care in nursing, we do not need to look far for examples of the consequences of nurses failing to uphold such an ethic. The widespread publicity that has been given to what has been variously called ‘a crisis of compassion’ ( Hehir 2013 : 109) and ‘crisis of care’ ( Darbyshire & McKenna 2013 : 305) in nursing in the UK is such an example. Drawing on the findings of a series of damning reports on the British health care system (circa 2011–13), this crisis has involved the graphic public portrayal of nurses as being ambivalent, insensitive, uncompassionate, disengaged and, worse, of causing distress, danger and even death to patients ( Darbyshire & McKenna 2013 ; Hehir 2013 ; Roberts & Ion 2014 ; Scott PA 2014 ). Scott is unequivocal in his supposition regarding what lies at the root of this crisis, namely: missing qualities of character or more specifically missing virtues of character ( Scott PA 2014 ). Virtues of character, he contends, are essential to the nurse’s ability to provide ‘constructive care’ – care that is patient oriented, committed, attentive, humanising and ‘rooted in the needs of the individual patient’ (p 177). To this end, the qualities of character (virtues) that nurses require need to be cultivated through education and role-modelling and, importantly, become embedded as ‘enduring dispositions of character’ approached from the perspective of ‘habituated good nursing behaviour’ vis-à-vis the excellences of nursing practice ( Scott PA 2014 : 177).


Problems with virtue ethics


Virtue ethics, like other theories of ethics, is not free of difficulties. Key among these are: the ‘circularity of justification’ in virtue theory (virtuous persons do what is good, the good is what virtuous persons do), the inability of virtue theory to explain adequately its force as a moral action guide (i.e. compared with other obligation-based theories that can rely on moral rules, principles and maxims to justify moral conduct), and the high expectations that virtue theory imposes on people to be ‘good’ (while a good many of us can be conscientious in our actions, few of us can be ‘exemplary’ ( Pellegrino 1995 : 262–3)). These difficulties, however, may be more a product of the adversarial nature of philosophical inquiry and its use to critically examine and raise objections to virtue theory, than a problem with virtue ethics itself. For instance, given the distinctive non-rational quality of the moral virtues, it seems odd to suggest that virtuous actions require ‘justification’. (How does one ‘justify’ an inclination to be kind towards another, or to be fair? How does one ‘justify’ an act of saintliness or heroism?) Similarly, it seems odd to expect that virtue theory can be reduced to a set of justificatory rules, principles and maxims (noting that what makes the virtues what they are is their often spontaneous and unconditional expression beyond that otherwise required by rules, principles and maxims). There is room here to suggest that to ‘justify’ the virtues in a rational philosophical sense is to do violence to them and to all that they represent. Finally, it seems odd to suggest that expecting people to be ‘decent’ and ‘morally excellent’ human beings is ‘too high an expectation’. Ethics is precisely about expecting people to strive to achieve the highest ideals of morality and to engage in morally excellent conduct. Virtue ethics is no different in this regard. That people may not achieve such an ideal is no reason to abandon ethics, and it is no reason to abandon virtue ethics either.


It is generally accepted that, although virtue theory cannot stand alone, it can be (and should be) ‘related to other ethical theories in a more comprehensive moral philosophy than currently exists’ ( Pence 1984 : 282; see also Pellegrino 1995 : 254). Over the past two decades, scholars have shown that, contrary to the criticisms that have conventionally been directed against it, virtue ethics and ‘the virtues’ do provide an account of right action. Moreover, like other obligation-based theories, virtue ethics also includes rules – what Hursthouse (1999 : 36) calls ‘v-rules’ (e.g. ‘do what is honest’, ‘do what is kind’, ‘do what is charitable’) – and thus is mostly compatible with traditional obligation-based theories (e.g. principles and rules). And where there exists a correspondence between virtue ethics (e.g. the virtues) and other moral theories (e.g. ethical principlism), even though ‘rough and imperfect’, they tend to be mutually reinforcing ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 : 381). For example, respect for the principle of autonomy requires the virtue of respectfulness, commitment to and upholding the principle of beneficence requires the virtue of benevolence, and upholding the principle of non-maleficence requires the virtue of non-malevolence ( Beauchamp & Childress 2013 : 381).


Deontology and teleology


This discussion on moral theory would not be complete without reference being made to two main ‘parent’ theories of ethics, namely: deontology and teleology (also called consequentialism, of which utilitarian theory is a form).


Deontology


‘Deontology’ comes from the Greek deon , meaning ‘duty’, and logos , meaning ‘word’ or ‘reasoned discourse’. According to deontological ethics, duty is the basis of all moral action. Taken at its most basic, the discourse of deontology asserts that some acts are obligatory (duty-bound) regardless of their consequences. For example, a deontologist might assert that one has a duty to always tell the truth. By this view, the deontologist is duty-bound to always tell the truth even when doing so might have horrible consequences. An important question to be asked here is: ‘How do we know what our duty is?’


One possible answer to this question can be found in classical deontological theory that derives from religious ethics. According to this view, it is God’s command that determines our moral duties. If, for example, God commands ‘thou shalt not kill’, ‘thou shalt not steal’ and the like, then conduct that accords with (obeys) these commands is morally praiseworthy (right and justified). This is ‘because and only because it is commanded by God’ ( Frankena 1973 : 28).


There are many examples of deontological ethics influencing decision-making in health care domains. For example, Jehovah’s Witnesses are well known for their refusal of life-saving blood transfusions, on the grounds that to accept such treatment would be tantamount to violating God’s command that, according to their beliefs, prohibits taking blood ( Fry & Johnstone 2008 ). Another example can be found in a deontological adherence by some physicians and surgeons to the preservation of ‘medically hopeless’ human life whatever the costs (read consequences) resulting in the administration of ‘futile’ medical treatment to patients – sometimes even against their will ( Schneiderman & Jecker 2011 ).


Another answer can be found in what is otherwise known as ethical rationalism. This view dates back to the work of the 18th century German philosopher Immanuel Kant, who held that the supreme principle of morality was reason, whose ultimate end is good will. According to a 1972 translation, Kant stated that reason is free (autonomous) to formulate moral law and to determine just what is to count as being an overriding moral duty. Kant held duty to be that which is done for its own sake, and ‘not for the results it attains or seeks to attain’ ( Kant 1972 : 20 (‘The formal principle of duty’, in original pp 13–14)). Kant further believed that moral considerations (duties) were always overriding in nature – in other words, should take precedence over other (non-moral) considerations.


In terms of determining what one’s actual duty is, Kant suggested that this can be done by appealing to some formal (reasoned) principle or maxim. In choosing such a maxim, however, Kant warned that we must take care not to choose something that would privilege our interests over the interests of others. Kant’s solution to this problem was to establish a universally valid law called the ‘categorical imperative’. This law states: ‘Act only on that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should become universal law’ ( Kant 1972 : 29 (‘The formula of universal law’, in original pp 51–2)). In other words, we should act only on maxims that we are prepared to accept as holding for everybody (including ourselves) throughout space and time. A variation of Kant’s law can be found in what is popularly known as the Golden rule: ‘Do unto others as you would have them do unto you’.


Teleology


‘Teleology’ comes from the Greek telos , meaning ‘end’, and logos , meaning ‘word’ or ‘reasoned discourse’. According to teleological theory (also known as consequentialism) actions can be judged right and / or good only on the basis of the consequences they produce. In this respect, discourse on teleological ethics denies everything that deontological ethics asserts.


The most popularly known teleological theory of ethics is utilitarianism , which has as its central concern the general welfare of people as a whole, rather than individuals. In short, utilitarianism views the world not in terms of certain individual rights, which people may or may not claim, but rather in terms of people’s collective and overall welfare and interests. The perspective of utilitarianism is persuasive in that it promotes a universal point of view – namely, that one person’s interests cannot count as being superior to the interests of another, just because they are personal interests ( Singer 1993 ; Smart & Williams 1973 ). To put this another way, I cannot claim that my interests are more deserving than your interests are, just because they are my interests.


Classical utilitarianism, first advanced by the English philosopher Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) and later modified by the work of the British philosopher John Stuart Mill (1806–73), holds roughly that moral agents have a duty to ‘maximise the greatest happiness / good for the greatest number’ ( Bentham 1962 ; Mill 1962 ). This view has resulted in classical utilitarianism being dubbed the ‘greatest happiness principle’. Because of difficulties associated with calculating both individual and collective happiness and unhappiness, and the problem of individual interests being sacrificed for the collective whole, classical utilitarianism theory has been largely abandoned in favour of more recent utilitarian theories. Of particular note is preference utilitarianism, which views the maximisation of autonomy and individual preferences as being of intrinsic value rather than the maximisation of happiness per se. This is because, as Beauchamp and Childress (2013 : 356) explain, what is intrinsically valuable is what individuals prefer to obtain, and utility is thus translated into maximising ‘the overall satisfaction of the preferences of the individuals affected’.


Although not without difficulty, preference utilitarianism is also considered more plausible since it is relatively easy to calculate what people’s preferences are: all we have to do is to ask people what it is they prefer. And where their preferences are at odds with ethical conduct, we have no obligation to respect them.


Moral duties and obligations


Common to all theoretical perspectives are the imperatives they impose for behaving in ways that respect the significant moral interests of others. It is generally accepted within moral philosophy that moral theories, moral principles and moral rights all provide sound moral reasons for deciding and acting (behaving) in certain ways towards others and for explaining why we should act morally. For example, the moral principle of autonomy and the moral right to informed consent both seem to provide strong reasons (‘moral warrants’) for giving information to patients / clients and why – that is, to enable them to make prudent and intelligent choices about their care and treatment. More than this, they impose a moral duty on us to do so. To understand what this means and how duties (and their counterparts, obligations) ‘bind’ us to be moral, it would be useful here to explain what duties and obligations are and how they work.


Moral duties


A moral duty (to be distinguished here from a legal duty, a civil duty, a professional duty and so on) is an action which a person is bound, for moral reasons, to perform. Language used in identifying duties typically involves expressions such as: ‘I have a duty to …’, ‘You have a duty to …’, ‘They have a duty to …’ and so on.


Duties are primarily concerned with avoiding intolerable results; they are thought to provide the basic requirements that may be demanded of everybody (i.e. universally) in an effort to achieve a ‘tolerable basis of social life’ ( Urmson 1958 , in Feinberg 1969 : 73). They also work ‘to secure reliability, a state of affairs in which people can reasonably expect others to behave in some ways and not in others’ ( Williams 1985 : 187). If a duty fails to avoid an intolerable result, there is room for questioning whether in fact it was a duty in the first place ( Urmson 1958 ). It might also be argued that if a duty can be overridden (e.g. where there appears to be a conflict of duties) it is not a duty at all; we have merely mistakenly thought that it was ( Hare 1981 : 26). On the other hand, it might be replied that just because a duty can be overridden this does not mean ‘it was not a duty in the first place’ but only that it was a ‘prima-facie duty’. There is nothing philosophically wrong in holding that duties can be prima facie in nature ( Ross 1930 : 19).


As already stated, moral reasons binding people to act in certain ways can be provided from the following sources: a moral theory, a moral principle or a moral right. For example, from a teleological perspective, duties generally derive from the consideration of some predicted moral consequence that ought to be furthered or upheld. It might be argued, for instance, that one has a stringent moral duty to prevent otherwise-avoidable harmful consequences from occurring where this can be done without sacrificing other important moral interests. Given this ‘teleological reason’, if a person’s action stands to prevent a particular harmful consequence from occurring, that person is duty-bound to perform that action, provided other important moral interests are not sacrificed in the process. An off-duty nurse, for example, could be said to be duty-bound to render life-saving care at the scene of a road accident, regardless of any inconvenience this might cause, since mere inconvenience is not generally regarded as a morally significant consideration. If the life of the nurse were put at risk, however, the moral duty to render assistance would not be so clear-cut.


Similarly in the case of ethical principlism – for example, the ethical principles of autonomy, non-maleficence, beneficence and justice all provide moral reasons binding people to act in certain ways towards others: the principle of autonomy, for instance, imposes on people a duty to respect the preferences and related decisions of others, the principle of non-maleficence imposes on people a duty not to harm others, the principle of beneficence imposes on people a duty to treat others well (beneficially), and the principle of justice imposes on people a duty to treat others fairly.


In a rights view of morality, and in contrast to the above approaches, a moral reason is supplied by a correlative rights claim. Thus if someone claims a right to be respected, this imposes on us a duty to respect that person; likewise, if someone claims a right to privacy, this imposes on us a duty not to disclose information of a private nature about that person, and so on.


The critical task for each of us is to decide just what our moral duties are. This, of course, is dependent on correctly determining what is to count as an overriding moral reason for doing something or, as in the case of rights, correctly determining whether a given rights claim is genuine and, further, whether we as moral agents do in fact have a duty correlative to the claim in question.


Moral obligations


A notion that is strongly related to the notion of ‘moral duty’ is that of ‘moral obligation’. The language of obligations is very similar to the language of duties, and typically involves expressions such as: ‘You have an obligation to …’, ‘I have an obligation to …’, ‘We have an obligation to …’, ‘They have an obligation to …’ and so on. Although many philosophers treat the terms ‘duties’ and ‘obligations’ synonymously, an important and useful distinction can be drawn between them, which rests on the differing moral strengths each notion has rather than on a difference in their essential moral nature. Duties are regarded as having a stronger force than obligations, or, to put this another way, duties are more morally compelling than are obligations. Dworkin (1977 : 48–9), an influential exponent of this distinction, gives the example that it is one thing to say a person has an obligation to give to a charity, but it is quite another to say that person has a duty to do so. Although it would be ‘good’ if someone made a charitable donation, it would be a mistake to suggest a moral compulsion to do so. To a limited extent, Dworkin’s thesis helps to alleviate the tension created by the problem of supposed conflicting duties.


The concept of obligation and its distinctiveness from duty has interesting and important implications for nurses, particularly in relation to the issue of following a doctor’s or a supervisor’s directives. For instance, it may well be that nurses have an obligation to follow a doctor’s or a supervisor’s directives, but it is far from clear that they always have a duty to do so, either morally or legally. In fact, if a doctor’s or a supervisor’s directives are ‘dubious’, a nurse has both a legal and a moral duty to question such directives. In some cases, the nurse may even have a duty to refuse to follow a given directive if, for instance, it is ‘unreasonable’, ‘unlawful’ or ‘unethical’ – for example, likely to cause otherwise avoidable harm.


Clarifying the difference between rights and duties


Before concluding this discussion, the important task remains of clearing up some confusion which some nurses may have about their own rights and duties in relation to caring for patients. Consider, for example, a situation involving an abortion procedure. A nurse could reasonably claim either a right to refuse to participate in an abortion procedure or a duty to refuse to participate. What is important here is to distinguish the basis upon which each claim might rest and to remember that, whereas rights basically concern claims about one’s own interests, duties basically concern claims about the interests of others. Thus, in an abortion case, if a nurse claims the right to refuse this is fundamentally a claim involving the protection of the nurse’s own interests (as opposed to the interests of the patient). The nurse might, for instance, have a religious-based conscientious objection to abortion and assert an entitlement to practise the tenets of that faith. A refusal based on a duty claim is significantly different, however. In this instance, the refusal is based more on the consideration of another’s interests – for example, the interests of the patient or the fetus. Here the duty to refuse would derive from the broader moral duty to, say, prevent harm or to preserve life.


By this brief account it can be seen that to use the terms ‘rights’ and ‘duties’ interchangeably is not only incorrect but misleading. When nurses speak of their right to, say, care for a patient in a certain way, or to practise their code of ethics, it is quite possible they are really asserting that they have a duty to care for the patient in that way or a duty to uphold their code of ethics.

Only gold members can continue reading. Log In or Register to continue

Stay updated, free articles. Join our Telegram channel

Oct 7, 2019 | Posted by in NURSING | Comments Off on Moral theory and the ethical practice of nursing

Full access? Get Clinical Tree

Get Clinical Tree app for offline access